Skip to main content

Full text of "Philosophy as scientia scientiarum : and, A history of classifications of the sciences"

See other formats


This is a digital copy of a book that was preserved for generations on library shelves before it was carefully scanned by Google as part of a project 
to make the world's books discoverable online. 

It has survived long enough for the copyright to expire and the book to enter the public domain. A public domain book is one that was never subject 
to copyright or whose legal copyright term has expired. Whether a book is in the public domain may vary country to country. Public domain books 
are our gateways to the past, representing a wealth of history, culture and knowledge that's often difficult to discover. 

Marks, notations and other marginalia present in the original volume will appear in this file - a reminder of this book's long journey from the 
publisher to a library and finally to you. 

Usage guidelines 

Google is proud to partner with libraries to digitize public domain materials and make them widely accessible. Public domain books belong to the 
public and we are merely their custodians. Nevertheless, this work is expensive, so in order to keep providing this resource, we have taken steps to 
prevent abuse by commercial parties, including placing technical restrictions on automated querying. 

We also ask that you: 

+ Make non-commercial use of the files We designed Google Book Search for use by individuals, and we request that you use these files for 
personal, non-commercial purposes. 

+ Refrain from automated querying Do not send automated queries of any sort to Google's system: If you are conducting research on machine 
translation, optical character recognition or other areas where access to a large amount of text is helpful, please contact us. We encourage the 
use of public domain materials for these purposes and may be able to help. 

+ Maintain attribution The Google "watermark" you see on each file is essential for informing people about this project and helping them find 
additional materials through Google Book Search. Please do not remove it. 

+ Keep it legal Whatever your use, remember that you are responsible for ensuring that what you are doing is legal. Do not assume that just 
because we believe a book is in the public domain for users in the United States, that the work is also in the public domain for users in other 
countries. Whether a book is still in copyright varies from country to country, and we can't offer guidance on whether any specific use of 
any specific book is allowed. Please do not assume that a book's appearance in Google Book Search means it can be used in any manner 
anywhere in the world. Copyright infringement liability can be quite severe. 

About Google Book Search 

Google's mission is to organize the world's information and to make it universally accessible and useful. Google Book Search helps readers 
discover the world's books while helping authors and publishers reach new audiences. You can search through the full text of this book on the web 



at jhttp : //books . qooqle . com/ 



PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SCIENTIAEUM 



AND 



A HISTORY OF CLASSIFICATIONS 
OF THE SCIENCES 



PHILOSOPHY AS SOIENTIA SOIENTIARUM 



AND 



A HISTOKY OF CLASSIFICATIONS 
OF THE SCIENCES 



BY 



ROBERT FLINT 

D.D., LL.D., F.R.8.S. 
ooBBnPOVDnro kxhbbb of thb uwtitot b or nuvcs ; 

HOTOBABY MEMBER OF TBS ROYAL SOC1KTT OF PALERMO J AKD 
PBOFBWOB (EMXEITUS), BCIVBUBGH UVnPBBBITY 



i * • 



WILLIAM BLACKWOOD AND SONS 

EDINBURGH AND LONDON 

MCMIV 



All Righto reserved 



121092 



PREFATORY NOTE. 



Very little requires to be referred to here. The Table 
of Contents should render unnecessary any Index of 
Names. The author's connection with the subject of 
his book has been a lengthened one. When a mere 
youth in Glasgow University he joined a number of 
young men, among whom were representative Cana- 
dians, Englishmen, Welshmen, and others, in forming 
a Literary and Philosophical Society. As a member 
and vice-president his contributions to it were two 
essays, one on " Cartesianism " and the other on " The 
Relations of the Sciences." The former cost him a 
study of two hundred old books in Latin and French, 
but it soon got lost and never returned to him. The 
latter he still possesses, and deems on the whole fairly 
accurate so far as it goes. His dealing with such a 
subject at all he attributes to the inspiration of the 
greatest of his teachers, the Professor William Thom- 
son of the time, the Lord Kelvin of to-day and of all 
time. My study on the " Relations of the Sciences " 
did not deal at all with the history of the subject, but 



VI PREFATORY NOTE. 

kept entirely to what was implied in the title. During 
some years I was entirely engrossed with pastoral 
duties. In 1864-65, my first session as Professor of 
Moral Philosophy and Political Economy at St An- 
drews, I gave some lectures on the connection of those 
two sciences to other sciences. In 1867 I had begun 
to think of constructing an elaborate work on the 
Relations of the Sciences to one another, to Philosophy, 
Religion, and Morality, and such a work was adver- 
tised for a considerable number of years. The delay 
and revocation must have been hard on the publishers, 
but I suppose publishers get accustomed to such things. 
For myself I deem it fortunate and even providential 
to have had to change my intended course and follow 
others where more urgent demands were made and 
more obvious interests were at stake. A considerable 
portion of the History of Classifications of the Scieiices 
appeared in America long prior to any portion of it in 
Britain. The portion referred to will be found in the 
July number of the Presbyterian Review for 1885. 
Dr Briggs and Dr Patton were the chief editors of the 
Review. Dr Calderwood, Dr Blaikie, Dr Croskery, 
and I were associate editors for Great Britain. Never 
can I forget the kindness and worthiness of them all. 
Alas 1 few of them now remain here below. May those 
of us who are still here walk worthy of those who 
have gone before. 

R. FLINT. 

1 Mountjoy Terrace, Musselburgh, N.B., 
24th September 1904. 



CONTENTS. 



PAon 

PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SCIENTIARUM 1-63 

I. Philosophy should supplement the sciences . 3-7 

It should trace aright their boundaries and relationships 7-12 

Should aid them effectively to co-operate. Examples . 12-16 

Needed to counteract excessive specialism. Examples . 16-18 

Bemarks on a passage of Wordsworth 19-21 

Philosophy should be a guide to education . . 21-23 

Truths between as important as truths within the sciences 24-28 

II. How philosophy should help to estimate aright the sciences 28-32 

Philosophy as Critical ..... 32-33 

as Metaphysical ..... 33-36 

as Practical ...... 37-38 

how different from ordinary knowledge or positive 

science ....... 38-41 

III. The various species of knowledge. Animal Mind 41-51 

Ordinary human knowledge . 51-52 

Scientific knowledge ..... 52-54 

Philosophic knowledge ..... 54-56 

Restatement of its stages or species 57-62 

Divine knowledge. Omniscience .... 62-63 



A HISTORY OF CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES 67-340 

First problem of ecientia ecientiarum — £&, positive 

philosophy ...... 67-68 

I. From Plato to the Renaissance . . 68-97 

The Platonic attempt at a distribution of knowledge. 

Erroneous views of it Its merits and defects 68-77 



Vlll 



CONTENTS. 



The Aristotelian scheme of classification so far an 
advance on the Platonic distribution of knowledge. 

Its encyclopaedic character .... 77-81 

Has three great defects . . 81-84 

Modified Aristotelian classification . . 84-86 

Stoic and Epicurean distribution of sciences . 86-88 

From Capella and Cassiodorus to Bonaventura and Dante 88-97 

II. From the Renaissance to Kant . . . 97-131 

In that interval were the classifications of Poliziano 

and Nizolio ...... 97-99 

OfCampanella . . .99-103 

OfDesCartes 103-104 

And of Bacon. For the Baconian distribution of 

science see ..... . 104-111 

For criticism of it . . . 111-113 
Albted's Encyclopaedias and the pansophic systems of 

Comenius and Weigel . . . . . 113-118 
Hobbes' classification of the sciences is in some respects 

superior to Bacon's . . . . .118-122 

Locke's division of them is much inferior to both 

Bacon's and Hobbes' ..... 122-124 
Leibniz showed it to be radically defective. His own 

was so likewise ..... 124-126 

Vico largely anticipated Comte .... 127-129 

Wolffianism essentially encyclopaedic 129-131 

III. From Kant to De Tract .... 132-161 

Kant's scheme of the sciences .... 132-134 

Objections to it ...... 134-135 

In Germany Sulzer, Gesner, Krug, and many others 
attempted to exhibit encyclopaedic surveys of the 

sciences ...... 135-141 

The English Cyclopaedia and the French EncyclopeaHe . 141-142 

IVAlembert's classification, and indication of its defects 142-147 

Rise of the Doctrine of Science. Fichte and Schelling . 147-153 

German distributions of the sciences from 1806 to 1816 153-154 

Hegel and his Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences 1 54- 1 60 

De Tracy and his Cows <$ Ideologic . 160-161 

IV. From Bentham to Gioberti .... 162-197 

Bent ham's classification formed by successive bifurca- 
tions like a Bamean tree .... 162-164 



CONTENTS. 



IX 



Coleridge's classification ..... 165-166 

Jannelli's general distribution .... 166-167 

Komagnosi, Longo, and Ventura . . . 167-170 

Ferrarese and De Pamphilis .... 170-173 

Neil Arnott'8 fourfold distribution and four funda- 
mental sciences ..... 173-175 

Comte's classification stated and criticised . 175-185 

Also Amperes ...... 185-191 

Proudhon's substitution of a ternary for Ampere's 

quaternary distribution .... 191-193 

Duval-Jouve's classification in his Traite* de Logique 

manifestly insufficient . . . 193 
Views of Bosmini and Gioberti on classification of the 
Sciences . . . 193-197 

V. From Whkwell to Zkller .... 197-239 

Whewell'8 classification elaborate but not always ration- 
ally connected ...... 197-202 

Views of Lubbock, Lindsay, and Ramsay . 202-203 
Schopenhauer's scheme of distribution of the sciences 

a very ingenious curiosity .... 203-204 

Dove's classification of the sciences well presented 204-208 

Objections to it ...... 208-213 

Cournot'8 co-ordination of the departments of human 

knowledge ...... 213-215 

Wilson's reproduction of the Aristotelian classification 215-216 
Hamilton's classification in Lectures on Metaphysics 

(LectVII.) 217-221 

Renouvier's scheme and its defects 221-224 
Peccenini's Nuovo Albero Enciclopedico and Di Gio- 
vanni's Principii di Filosofia Prima 224-226 
Spencer's classification stated and criticised 227-238 
Zeller and Harms ..... 239 

VI. From Bain to Wundt ..... 239-272 

Bain's classification an improvement on Comte's and 

superior to Spencer's ..... 239-244 

Cantoni'8 Corso> Valdarnini's Ptincipio, &c., and Pey- 

retti's Istituzioni, &c. . . . . . 244-247 

Labanca'8 three classes of sciences. See his Dialettica 

(vol. ii. lib. iv. c. i.) 247-249 

Conti's 11 Vero nelV Ordine (2 vols. c. xi.) . 249-250 

B. Erdmann's " Gliederung der Wissenschaf ten " 250-253 



X CONTENTS. 

Corleo's Sophology in his Sistema ddla FUosqfia Univer- 
sale ...... 253-254 

Bourdeau's single linear series of fundamental sciences 254-255 

Prof. Shield's Order of the Sciences . . . 255-259 
H. M. Stanley's Classification of the Sciences, in Mind\ 

No. XXXIV 259-261 

D. G. Thompson's scheme in his System of Psychology 

(vol. i. pp. 76, 77) 262-263 

DeRoberty's/ourgrrowp* .... 263-267 
Wundtfs conclusions as to the classification of the 

sciences ...... 267-272 

VII. From Masartk to Karl Pearson 272-301 

Masaryk's Versuch einer Concreten Logik 272-283 
Adrien Naville's classification of the sciences . . 283-289 
De la Grasserie's De la classification objective et sub- 
jective des sciences, &c. 289-292 
Karl Pearson's classification of the sciences in his 

Grammar of Science ..... 292-301 

Criticisms of .... . 293, 295, 299, 300 

VIII. From Paul Janet to Present Time . . . 301-340 

How Janet has dealt with classification of the sciences 301-306 

Goblot'8 "system of the sciences" . . . 307-315 

Stadler's contribution to organisation of the sciences . 315-320 

Trivero's Classifications delle Scienze . . . 320-324 
Durand's study of Taxinomy — *'.«., of classification 

itself 324-326 

History of classification of the sciences will not be 

arrested ...... 326-327 

Influence of Anthropology, Ethnology, and Sociology 

on organisation of the sciences . 328-338 

Of Anthropology ..... 328-334 

Of Ethnology ...... 335 

Of Sociology ...... 335-338 

Concluding Words ..... 338-340 



PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SCIENTIAEUM 



PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SCIENTIARUM. 



I. 

rpHE sciences are parts of a great whole, the 
members of a magnificent system. Each of 
them has manifold relations to every other. But 
the great whole, the magnificent system, to which 
they belong is itself an object of knowledge. 
Unless the intellectual universe be no real uni- 
verse, but essentially a chaos, science must be 
general as well as special ; or, in other words, there 
must be a science of the sciences — a science which 
determines the principles and conditions, the limits 
and relations, of the sciences. This science is 
philosophy ; and what the author has to say in the 
present chapter is meant to be a plea for philosophy 
as the legitimate but often disavowed and insulted 
queen of the sciences. "Time was," says Kant, 
"when metaphysics was the queen of all the 
sciences. But now it is the fashion to heap con- 



4 PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SCIENTIARUM. 

tempt and scorn upon her, and the matron mourns, 
forlorn and forsaken, like Hecuba." The sciences, 
however, cannot do without a queen. There may 
be a republic of letters, but the sciences cannot 
constitute a republic; they must be so connected 
as to form a unity; and the science which refers 
them to unity and shows that knowledge as a 
whole is a cosmos is the supreme science, the queen 
of the sciences. The want of practical recognition 
of this truth is one main cause of the intellectual 
anarchy of our times. 

Philosophy as scientia scientiarum may have 
more functions than one, but it has at least one. 
It has to show how science is related to science, 
where one science is in contact with another, in 
what way each fits into each, so that all may 
compose the symmetrical and glorious edifice of 
human knowledge, which has been built up by the 
labours of all past generations, and which all future 
generations must contribute to perfect and adorn. 
With whatever province of science a thoughtful 
man occupies himself, he soon becomes aware that 
it has intimate and manifold connections with other 
provinces, and if he try to trace these connec- 
tions out, he will ere long perceive that the sciences 
are not isolated things, but so bound together as 
to constitute a unity which is a reflection of the 
unity of nature and of the unity of that Supreme 



PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SCIEXTIABUM. 5 

Reason which pervades all nature and originates all 
intelligence. Philosophy aims to raise the mind 
gradually and legitimately to a point from which 
this unity may be visible, while the distinctions of 
the special sciences are not only not effaced, but 
lie clearly and truthfully before it. If I seek to 
vindicate and magnify this aim it is not because I 
suppose its reasonableness is likely to be directly 
and explicitly denied, but because its importance 
can scarcely in the present day be too often or 
strongly insisted on. There is many a truth which 
is not contested, which receives a ready acqui- 
escence of a sort, and yet which is very far from 
being apprehended or generally acted on, because 
the evidence for it is not so definitely and ade- 
quately before the mind as to counteract influences 
which tend to obscure it and make it practically 
neglected. And that aspiration after insight into 
the system of science as a whole should not be lost 
in the study of details is pre-eminently such a truth. 

Now, the first consideration which here suggests 
itself is that philosophy, viewed as scientia scienti- 
arum, is simply science which has attained to a 
knowledge of the unity, self-consistency, and har- 
mony of the teachings of the separate sciences. 
Philosophy seeks to do for the sciences just what 
each science does for the doctrines it comprehends. 



6 PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SGIENTIARUM. 

In the latter case separate truths are brought into 
unity, and in the former separate sciences. The 
one unity constitutes a science, the other a science 
of the sciences, and shows that absolutely there is 
but one science, although it has various depart- 
ments, whereby the incommensurableness of nature 
is brought down to our capacities. The second and 
higher unity is as natural, as legitimate, as im- 
portant as the first and lower unities. It would 
little avail, indeed, that these existed — that there 
was unity enough in things to permit of the forma- 
tion of special sciences — if there were no still more 
comprehensive unity, if the point of view of each 
science was in itself final, if each science was utterly 
isolated from all others. If such were the case 
there would be in science something essentially dis- 
appointing to the human mind, for it would be of 
its very nature calculated not to satisfy but to 
thwart that love of unity which is the source and 
life of all scientific research. If such were the case 
truth would not form a fair and harmonious body, 
but it would resemble the mangled and scattered 
limbs of Osiris, while the human mind in its pursuit 
would be engaged in a task more mournful than 
that of Isis, because hopeless. It is not so, how- 
ever, but 

" The One through all in cycles goes, 
And all to One returning flows." 



PHILOSOPHY A8 SCIENTIA SCIENTIARUM. 7 

Science is not sectioned into entirely unconnected 
sciences. In all the sciences there is a certain 
common nature, and among them there are many 
ties of affinity and points of contact. There are 
precedence and subordination, order and harmony, 
among them; so that, many and diverse as they 
are, they form a whole, a system in which each of 
them has its appropriate place, and, so far from 
being sacrificed to any other, has a new dignity 
imparted to it by being referred to the final unity 
of reason, the common centre of knowledge. 

Secondly, philosophy, as a comprehensive survey 
of the sciences and a deeply grounded knowledge 
of their principal relations to one another, is a 
condition indispensable to a correct conception of 
the special province of any science. The bound- 
aries of most sciences are very ill-traced, their 
definitions most irreconcilable. The first question 
which the student of any science naturally asks, 
What is it? What is it about? is one to which 
he can often get no satisfactory answer— one on 
which he finds that all the doctors disagree. Take 
logic. One logician will tell you its proper object 
is thought as thought ; another, that it is the forms 
as contradistinguished from the contents or matter 
of thought ; another, that it is only the necessary 
as distinct from the contingent forms of thought; 



8 PHILOSOPHY AS SCIBNTIA SOIENTIARUM. 

another, that it is only a kind of thought, mediate 
or discursive thought ; another, that it is only a 
kind of mediate or discursive thought — inference ; 
and still another, that it is not thought as thought, 
nor any elements or kinds of thought, but qualities 
of thought — truth and error so far as involved in 
the application of thought. And, it must be re- 
marked, this opposition is in no way one between 
old and new views, between transcended and effete 
conceptions and those which actually prevail, but 
one which exists between the most deliberately 
formed convictions of the most eminent modern 
logicians. Certainly it is a somewhat perplexing 
puzzle to lie at the very entrance of a science. 
The ingenuous youth who makes his first acquaint- 
ance with logic by getting that nut thrust into his 
mouth is not likely, if his teeth be sharp enough to 
crack it, to find any subsequent problem too hard 
for him. It is not much otherwise with psychol- 
ogy, with rhetoric, with ethics, with politics, with 
political economy. And as to metaphysics, it fares 
far worse; the discordance and embroilment there 
baffle description, for, as Professor Ferrier so happily 
said, " All the captains are sailing on different tacks, 
under different orders, and under different winds ; 
and each is railing at the others because they will 
not keep the same course with himself. One man 
is playing at chess, his adversary is playing against 



PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SCIENTIARUM. 9 

him at billiards ; and whenever a victory is achieved 
or a defeat sustained, it is always such a victory as 
a billiard-player might be supposed to gain over a 
chess-player, or such a defeat as a billiard-player 
might be supposed to sustain at the hands of a 
chess-player." 

Now, how is such a state of things to be 
remedied ? How are we to decide between the dis- 
putants ? How make a choice for ourselves between 
conflicting definitions ? It is obvious neither tradi- 
tion nor authority can here help us, for not only are 
they in themselves discordant and undecided, but 
they have no right to overrule reason, which ought 
to submit to evidence alone, and is unworthy of 
itself when it listens to any other voice than that of 
truth. Nor will it suffice to found our definitions 
on the etymology and inherent significance of 
names. That may wholly mislead. Words often 
come to signify what is altogether different from 
their intrinsic meaning, sometimes what is the 
reverse of it. A manufacture, for instance, is not 
what is made by the hand, but what is made 
by machinery with little or no aid from the 
hand. Words may be stretched or contracted, where 
needful, to conform to realities, but realities are 
not to be twisted in any way to conform to words ; 
and it is not with words but realities that science 
has to deal. It may be said, a science cannot be 



10 PHILOSOPHY AS SCI EN TI A SCIENTIARUM. 

defined until after the study of its appropriate facts, 
and when the study is sufficiently advanced the 
definition comes of itself. And that is so far true. 
Although first in the order of exposition, the defini- 
tion of a science is late in the order of discovery 
and presupposes a certain acquaintance with an 
appropriate order of facts, expressing, as it does, 
some essential characteristic which they all possess. 
But the question is, the difficulty is, to determine 
what is the appropriate order of facts, why the one 
chosen and not another, why an order of a given 
extent instead of one larger or smaller. All the 
views of logic, for instance, to which I have referred 
assign to it a natural order of facts, a sphere of real 
knowledge worth acquiring, a sphere with distinct 
enough boundaries ; and yet the natural orders 
are not coincident, the boundaries are altogether 
different, some going all round those of others, 
and others intersecting one another in the most 
perplexing ways. 

Now, in such a case, it is obvious there is but 
one mode of deciding who is right and who is 
wrong, who has selected the proper group of facts 
and who groups larger or smaller, who has traced 
the boundaries of his science well and who ill. It is 
by examining whose views give to their science a 
place that fits in rightly into the scheme of science. 
The question is one of adjustment. The logician 



PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SCIENTIABUM. 11 

simply as logician cannot define logic, for that is an 
affair of the settlement of boundaries between the 
sort of knowledge he cultivates and contiguous 
divisions of knowledge, such as metaphysics, 
psychology, and rhetoric; one, accordingly, which 
can only be decided by a higher and more general 
sort of considerations than belongs to any special 
science — by considerations as to the relations of the 
sciences. And this holds universally. It is as 
impossible to fix the position of a science without 
reference to neighbouring sciences, and even to the 
general system of the sciences, as to fix the position 
of a nation without reference to surrounding nations, 
and even to the general geography of the earth. In 
this respect a general scheme of science is exactly 
like a general map or like a terrestrial globe ; and 
like such map or globe it supplies a want which can 
no otherwise be provided for. An atlas with a 
separate map of every state in the world cannot 
dispense with, cannot supply the place of, a map 
which will show them in relation; nay, the more 
complete an atlas is in special maps the more need 
is there of a general one, because the more certainly 
and the more deeply will the student without such 
assistance be lost in details. And so with respect 
to science. The more it becomes divided and sub- 
divided, the more urgent, the more imperative 
becomes a knowledge of its greater general outlines 



12 PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA 8CIENTIARUM. 

in order that each man may recognise how the 
department he is specially conversant with is related 
to others. The greater the multiplication of sciences 
the more chaotic must be the effect they produce 
unless the mind can locate them aright, can refer 
them to their place in a system, and see how they 
stand to one another and the whole. 

What has now been said leads to a third 
consideration in favour of philosophy as viewed 
from our present standpoint. By a true co-ordina- 
tion of the sciences and a comprehensive insight 
into their natures, it must help us to see how 
and when they can assist each other. There are 
problems which require a combination of sciences 
for their solution ; there are certain combinations 
of the sciences possible, while others are absurd ; 
and it is only through a clear apprehension of the 
respective natures and relations of any two or 
more sciences that we can perceive if one can be 
made to operate with another to the attainment 
of a given end. Some of the most important 
advances which have occurred in the history of 
science have been due to the associated action of 
two or more sciences. A signal instance is 
Descartes' application of the algebraic analysis to 
define the nature and investigate the properties of 
curve lines. It was only by the clearest conception 



PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SG1ENTIARUM. 13 

of the relations of the two sciences, algebra and 
geometry, that he could have brought the symbols 
and calculations of the one to bear on the problems 
of the other, and thus start a new epoch in mathe- 
matical science. A more modern instance of the 
same kind is the union of chemistry and optics in 
spectral analysis, by which the most singularly 
interesting results as to the physical constitution 
of the heavenly bodies have been attained. It will 
be in the future as it has been in the past. Some 
of the most difficult and important of the problems 
which are at present attracting the curiosity and 
trying the ingenuity of men can only, it is apparent, 
find their solution from a happy combination of 
chemistry and physiology; others still more vital 
only from the combination of physiology and psy- 
chology ; and not a few are so complex that it is vain 
to hope that they will be mastered otherwise than 
by the conjoint and concentrated efforts of many 
sciences. It is most erroneous to suppose, as some 
persons do, that the true way to advance any study 
is to devote the whole mind exclusively to it so as 
to have no thought or interest beyond it. 

The sciences advance by solving problems which 
are often presented to them from without, and by 
accepting hints and helps from all sides. Mathe- 
matics itself, although it has in the character of 
its fundamental conceptions an enormous advantage 



14 PHILOSOPHY AS 8CIBNTIA SCI EN TI A RUM. 

over all other knowledge as abstract science, has 
found its chief stimulus in the requirements of the 
natural philosopher, in the problems of astronomy, 
mechanics, optics, heat, and electricity. " The 
combinations arising out of external phenomena," 
said Principal J. D. Forbes of St Andrews, "are 
more suggestive of the possible relations of number 
and quantity than is the most unlimited stretch of 
fancy and imagination." And if even mathematics, 
which is based on such singularly simple, precise, 
definable, workable conceptions as number and 
quantity, thus needs light from without, and only 
prospers because readily responsive to external 
suggestions, what can be expected from, say, logic, 
psychology, or ethics, which have vastly vaguer 
conceptions to start from, attempting to proceed 
entirely from within, and ignoring the combinations 
of human nature which are presented to us in 
history, in literature, and in language; what but 
that which we not unfrequently see — men working 
their way laboriously and painfully into a world of 
mere formulae, of words and nothing but words, 
although doubtless big and brave words — a region 
of absolute emptiness, into which we may as well 
not follow them, however much we may admire 
the strength of constitution which enables such 
privileged natures to sustain life in a vacuum? 
Whatever may be fancied to the contrary, the 



PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA 8CIENTIARUM. 15 

truth is that the researches and studies of the mere 
specialist are never very productive. Special in- 
vestigations only enrich science to any considerable 
extent when they are directed and guided by 
enlarged views; they are only truly successful 
when not exclusively special ; when, on the contrary, 
the part or section of existence examined is looked 
at by a reason illumined by a worthy and ample 
idea of science ; a reason which sees the part in the 
light of the whole and the whole as related to the 
part. I do not deny that now and then, by a 
lucky chance, a mere specialist may come across 
something valuable ; that an entomologist who has 
no interest in anything but beetles may detect 
something in the eye or on the wing of some of 
these creatures which wiser men than himself can 
turn to good account ; or that the most unintelligent 
local antiquarian may not find in some old document 
or mound or ruin a fact which decides the fate of a 
brilliant historical hypothesis : but I do affirm that 
discoveries thus made are extremely rare. Have 
not the most minute researches of recent botanists, 
zoologists, physiologists, &c, had reference to the 
vast generalisations and bold conjectures of a Spencer 
and a Darwin ? What special historical researches 
have ended in the adequate solution of a complicated 
and difficult problem, except those conducted by 
men whose insight into the general providential 



16 PHILOSOPHY AS SCIKNTIA SCIBNTIARUM. 

plan of history, or at least of a large portion 
of history, was clearer and more profound than 
that of other men ? I know of none. Now, what 
does all that amount to, but just that a study, a 
science, is progressive and flourishing only in so far 
as it is impelled and guided, penetrated and per- 
vaded, by the spirit of philosophy ; that all scientific 
discoveries whatever lie in the path along which 
philosophy leads science — along which science tends 
towards philosophy ? 

Philosophy, understood as has been explained, is, 
I remark fourthly, fitted and needed to counteract 
the evil intellectual and moral influences of special- 
ism. We are all narrow by nature, and we require 
to have our narrowness guarded against and cor- 
rected, not confirmed and intensified. Different 
minds have different natural aptitudes. These 
different aptitudes find their appropriate spheres 
of exercise in special studies and special depart- 
ments of practical life. A man with a genius for 
languages may have no turn for mathematics. The 
born poet may be the reverse of specially qualified 
for success either in science or business. The 
shrewdness and decision of mind which go so far 
to ensure success in the commercial world are 
useful gifts anywhere, but will certainly count 
for less in the world of learning than of traffic. 



PHILOSOPHY AS SCIBNTIA SCIENTIARUM. 17 

Many a man who is great, and justly great, 
among the merchant princes of the earth, could 
never have been educated into a great scholar or 
great speculative thinker, and that not from want 
of mind but from constitutional peculiarities of 
mind. Now, all such variety is wise and good. 
It makes human nature so much the fuller revela- 
tion of the divine nature ; human life so much the 
broader; human history so much the richer. But 
the same facts which show most distinctly how wide 
are the thoughts of God are those which also show 
most distinctly how narrow are the thoughts of men. 
Individuals will have it that their excellences 
are the only excellences — the pursuits which they 
prefer those which all men ought to prefer. 
The poet looks down on the man of business as a 
creature of low and grovelling habits, and the latter 
in turn casts a sarcastic glance upwards to his 
aerial friend, with the suspicion that he must find 
his castles in the air, even by moonlight, very 
poor places to live in. The distinguished classical 
scholar need not be ashamed that he cannot stand 
high in mathematics, yet he ought humbly to feel 
that his failure is owing to the limitations of his 
own individual intellect : but how apt is he instead 
to attribute to mathematics the restrictions which 
are in himself; to despise them, instead of learning 
the true lesson to be drawn from every failure 

B 



18 PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SOIENTIARUM. 

where we have earnestly striven to succeed — a due 
sense of one's own littleness. So the mathemati- 
cian, making his own individuality the measure of 
the whole universe of truth and culture, is prone 
to contemn many of the inquiries of the philologist 
as instances of learned trifling beneath the notice 
of serious men. Physicists and psychologists have 
never been noted for a candid appreciation of each 
other's labours. Any unfortunate science which 
happens to be not quite so strong as could be 
wished, metaphysics for instance, is almost sure to 
be fiercely set on by all the others, just as a poor, 
lame, unpopular swan is occasionally assailed by 
the whole flock of its companions. Now, there is 
only one judgment, I think, to be formed of all 
aversion of this sort, be it directed against what 
object it may. All such aversion is evil. It is a 
narrow and bad feeling which we ought to beware 
of cherishing. Sectarianism in science, like sec- 
tarianism in religion, is unlovely in itself and 
baneful in its consequences. Just as nothing is 
morally so ruinous as cultivating a habit of detect- 
ing only the faults and failings of our fellow-men, 
so nothing is intellectually more ruinous than 
cherishing a habit of depreciation of any kind of 
knowledge whatever. As in the moral life, al- 
though we cannot attain to all good, we ought 
carefully to cherish the love of all good, so in the 



PHILOSOPHY AS 8CIENTIA 8CIBNTIARUM. 19 

intellectual life, although we cannot attain to all 
truth, we ought carefully to cherish the love of all 
truth. But this, I need hardly say, is very difficult 
to do in the present state of society, when the 
division of scientific as well as of industrial func- 
tions is extreme. 

A great and thoughtful poet, struck with the 
obvious and terrible dangers which, in consequence, 
threaten the spiritual life, has said : 

" .... Go demand 
Of mighty nature if 'twas ever meant 
That we should pry far off and be unraised, 
That we should pore, and dwindle as we pore, 

Viewing all objects unremittingly 
In disconnection dead and spiritless ; 
And still dividing, and dividing still, 
Break down all grandeur, still unsatisfied 
With the perverse attempt, while littleness 
May yet become more little : waging thus 
An impious warfare 'gainst the very life 
Of our own souls." 

Now truth and error are mingled there and must 
be separated. It was meant by mighty nature that 
we should go on, as we have been doing, "still 
dividing, and dividing still"; it was meant that 
we should break down all grandeur into its consti- 
tuents ; that the life which we cannot create we 
should yet in order to understand dissolve into its 
elements and view them unremittingly, " dead and 



20 PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SCIENTIARUM. 

spiritless " although they be ; that we should be 
unsatisfied " while littleness may yet become more 
little," while division has not reached its utmost 
limits, while analysis has anything more to do. 
Division, analysis, is a necessary and inevitable 
condition of progress both in life and science. 
Every stage of progress must be consequent on a 
stage of division, spontaneous or reflective, indus- 
trial or scientific. We can well forgive a poet 
being slow to believe in the existence of such a 
law ; but the law exists, and it will not avail us to 
ignore it, still less to resist it. This law, however, 
like every other, requires to be watched and its 
incidental evils guarded against. It is not more 
true that it is one of the conditions on which the 
progress of science and the advancement of society 
depend, than that if left to itself, if not balanced 
and counteracted by other agencies, it will arrest 
science and destroy society. But nature has pro- 
vided forces with which it has only to be rightly 
adjusted in order that its action may be purely 
beneficial. If in one respect the subdivision of in- 
dustrial labour has a narrowing and anti-social influ- 
ence, it has in the other respect, that it condenses 
population within narrow circuits, associates intel- 
ligences and forces, and multiplies the objects of 
common interest, as well as the occasions for sym- 
pathy and the facilities for education, an influence 



PHILOSOPHY AS SCIKNTIA 8CIENTTARUM. 21 

altogether contrary, which has only to be made the 
most of and secured to the side of truth and good- 
ness in order that all the evils incident to the 
specialisation of functions in modern industry may 
be scarcely recognisable when laid by the side of its 
benefits. In a general doctrine of science, the ex- 
pression of that pure love of truth in its entirety 
which is identical with the spirit of philosophy, there 
is no less obviously a natural remedy for the evils 
incident to the specialisation of the sciences. Such 
a doctrine would enable the specialist to transcend 
the bounds of his own department, to realise his 
relation to science as a whole, and his own relation 
to all his fellow-labourers in science. Limited as his 
own particular study might be, it would no longer 
be a something " dead and disconnected," but united 
to the ultimate principles which are the root of all 
science, and through that union filled with the life 
which the root alone supplies. 

This leads me to remark that philosophy, thus 
viewed, would afford the most important guidance in 
education. It must be, indeed, the very basis of 
rational education in science. It must be what best 
determines the course to be pursued. We cannot 
commence the study of science at any point nor 
prosecute it in any order we please. Nature has 
determined both where we ought to begin and what 
path we ought to follow. It is very far from a 



22 PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SCIENTIARUM. 

matter of indifference which of the mathematical 
sciences we commence with. If we plunge into 
natural philosophy without any mathematics to buoy 
us up we are likely soon to repent of our fool- 
hardiness, and are certain not to swim very far. We 
shall make a similar mistake if we enter on moral 
philosophy without having made ourselves acquainted 
with the leading truths of psychology. Now, a phil- 
osophy of science worthy of what it should be would 
inform us at once what science was the natural ante- 
cedent of any other science, the condition of its intel- 
ligibility. It would, in fixing the order of the 
sciences, fix likewise the order of their rational study. 
It would thus lay what is the very corner-stone of 
the science of education — that without which no 
such thing as a science of education can exist. And 
it would confer on education another advantage only 
inferior to that. It would show what science was 
most fitted to correct the mental vices generated by 
any other science, as well as what science was needed 
to render it intelligible. No one science does more 
than cultivate the mind in a partial and one-sided 
manner; and if we would have fully developed, 
well-balanced minds, we must not only not confine 
ourselves exclusively to one, but counteract that 
which is exclusive and hurtful in our special pursuit 
by the kind of knowledge most unlike it in char- 
acter and tendencies ; that which it requires the most 



PHILOSOPHY AS SCIBNTIA SCIENTOARUM. 23 

directly opposite procedure of mind to appropriate ; 
that which exercises with most intensity the faculties 
which the other leaves most dormant. 

Those who cultivate a science which is entirely 
inductive, which is only in process of formation, 
still unsettled in its foundations, still vague and 
dubious in the majority of its conclusions, while they 
can need no mathematics merely to render it intel- 
ligible, are precisely those who will need most the 
peculiar discipline of mathematics ; and without it 
their power of deduction will remain unexercised; 
without it the very notion of what complete proof is 
will never find a place in their minds. On the same 
principle, the study of physics and psychology should 
be conjoined in one culture. The one is required to 
balance the other. All physicists should seek a 
general acquaintance with psychology, and all psy- 
chologists a general acquaintance with physics. This 
would remove the unbecoming antagonism which 
has so long and widely prevailed between those two 
classes of students — an antagonism which has its 
origin in ignorance, and is a signal proof of the 
narrowness of intellectual conception and illiber- 
ally of feeling which are produced by specialism 
when left to operate without check or counter- 
poise. This, then, is also to be said on behalf of 
a science of the sciences, that it would at once 
and authoritatively tell where the knowledge 



24 PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SOIENTIARUM. 

requisite to condition or the knowledge requisite 
to supplement or balance any other knowledge 
was to be found. 

I now come to a consideration at least as weighty 
as any of those which have already been mentioned 
— namely, the interest and importance of the truths 
with which a science of the sciences must be con- 
versant. The truths which lie between the sciences 
are as real and have equal claims to attention as the 
truths within the sciences. If the relations between 
facts are as important as the facts themselves, — and 
every science acknowledges and proceeds on this 
assumption, — how should the relations between the 
sciences not be of extreme interest and value? 
When these relations are known, all the facts any 
given special sciences deal with, and all the laws 
which have been derived from these facts, have a 
new light shed on them by being connected, con- 
trasted, and compared from an elevation which per- 
mits of a truthful survey. That the relations of 
the sciences to one another are in themselves most 
worthy of examination, any one may convince him- 
self by considering for a moment what they are, 
what great problems they present, what grave in- 
terests they involve. How are the mathematical 
sciences related to one another and to physics ? Do 
they originate in experience, or are they offshoots 
of a transcendental or metaphysical condition ? Are 



PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SCIENTIARUM. 25 

there any limits in nature to their application, and, 
if so, what are those limits ? These are questions 
which mathematics suggests, although it does not 
solve, — hard and abstruse but real and not fanciful, 
weighty and not trivial questions, — and on which 
not philosophers only, but men whose distinctions 
have been gained chiefly in mathematics, such as 
Courtot, Sir Wm. R. Hamilton of Dublin, Boole, 
De Morgan, Bartholmai, Duhamel, have written 
either books or elaborate essays. How are the 
physical sciences related? Which are simple and 
fundamental, which complex and applicate ? What 
must each take from others, and what may each be 
made to contribute to others? These, again, are 
questions which all physicists, not dwarfed by ex- 
clusive specialism of pursuit into incapacity of large 
views of any kind, are keenly alive to ; for they see 
that on clear and correct views regarding them the 
future progress of physical science is greatly depend- 
ent, and a right settlement of the practical problem, 
What is a wise and well-conducted education in 
physical science ? entirely dependent. What is the 
relation of the physical to the mental sciences, or 
even merely, What is the relation of physiology to 
psychology ? No man can be so intellectually blind 
as to fail to perceive what a most momentous ques- 
tion this is. Every thinking man must answer it in 
some form or way ; yet if you answer it in one way 



26 PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA 8CIENTIARUM. 

you must be a materialist, if in another a pure ideal- 
ist, and it is to be hoped that it can be answered 
also in a third way which will make you neither — 
which will not compel you, as a rational being, to 
deny the existence either of matter or spirit, either 
of your bodies or souls. 

Then, as to the mental sciences, psychology, ethics, 
aesthetics, politics, paideutics, philology, philosophy 
of history, &c, nothing is more certain than that a 
very large proportion of the evils which infest them, 
and which have given such abundant occasion to 
their adversaries to misrepresent and depreciate 
them, are due precisely to the want of definite and 
correct views in their cultivators as to their bound- 
aries and relations ; so that inquiries proper to one 
have been inextricably mixed up with inquiries 
proper only to another, and not unfrequently even 
this has been aggravated and confusion itself still 
further confounded by the introduction of the still 
more extraneous elements of physics, and meta- 
physics, and religion. 

There is not less involved in the question, How is 
metaphysics related to physical and mental science ? 
There are those who suppress metaphysics entirely, 
who regard it as only an erroneous phase of thought, 
gradually drawing near to the death which is its 
doom, — who maintain that there is no science save 
realistic or positive science. There are others who, 



PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA 8CIBNTIARUM. 27 

instead of thus absorbing metaphysics in positive 
science, have sought to absorb all positive science 
in metaphysics, pretended to " re- think the great 
thought of creation," and hesitated not to deny 
the law of gravitation, to blame the very stars, 
to pronounce the most ancient heavens wrong, 
when these things did not appear to conform 
to their deductions. And between these two ex- 
tremes, the Comtist and the Hegelian, there are 
innumerable other erroneous positions, into any 
of which it is easy to fall ; while to get sure 
footing on the one right spot no man can, unless 
by working out for himself a correct and adequate 
apprehension of the relation of metaphysics to 
experience. 

Quite as important as the question just referred 
to is this other question, How are piety and 
knowledge, religion and philosophy, theology and 
the physical and mental sciences, to be shown in 
their true relationship? Even in this age of 
many wants there are few, if any, more to be 
desired than a right answer to that question. The 
false and mischievous attitudes so often assumed 
by scientific men towards religion and by religious 
men towards science may unquestionably be largely 
traced to such erroneous conceptions of the relation- 
ship between religion and science as can only be 
dispelled by a thorough and unprejudiced philo- 



28 PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SCIENTIARUM. 

sophical investigation. And it can hardly be in 
the power of man to render better service to 
either religion or science than to exhibit them in 
their true natures and relationships, seeing that 
both of them, and society as well, are so grievously 
suffering from the want of clear and just views 
on the subject. 



II. 



In seeking to attain self-consistency and com- 
pleteness philosophy must strive to solve four 
very comprehensive and complex problems. 

In the first place, it has a duty towards the 
special sciences. 

It is bound to form a right estimate of them 
and to take up a right attitude towards them. 
It is science, yet not merely a special science, but 
the science which has the processes and results 
of all the special sciences for its data — the general 
or universal science which has so risen above the 
special and particular in science as to be able to 
contemplate the sciences as parts of a system 
which reflects and elucidates a world of which 
the variety is not more wonderful than the unity. 
Philosophy should neither attempt to do the work 
nor to dispense with the aid of any special science, 
but must seek so to understand the methods, to 



PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SCIENTIARUM. 29 

appreciate the findings, and to trace the relation- 
ships of all the special sciences as to be able to 
combine them into a harmonious cosmos or well- 
proportioned corpus. When engaged in this task 
it may appropriately and usefully, perhaps, be 
called positive philosophy, and nearly corresponds 
to what has been so designated by Comte. 

Comte's view of philosophy, however, as merely* 
a generalisation of the results of the sciences, 
would have been an inadequate one even if he had 
duly recognised the existence and claims of the 
psychological and theological sciences. It is 
necessary to hold to the truth which is in Kant's 
view, and to the truth which is in Ferrier's or 
Hegel's view, of the nature of philosophy, quite 
as firmly as to the truth which is in Comte's view. 
Given a complete knowledge of the relations of the 
sciences — given, consequently, a correct picture on 
the mind's eye of the whole intelligible world drawn 
from the highest and best established results of all 
the sciences — and the work of reason, which is the 
comprehension of itself and of its objects so far as 
knowable, is still far from accomplished; yea, its 
highest and perhaps hardest labours have not yet 
begun. Scientific thought is not necessarily self- 
criticising thought ; on the contrary, mere scientific 
thought, however rigid and methodical, is essentially 
dogmatic thought in that it rests on untested and 



30 PHILOSOPHY AS SCIKNTIA SCIBNTIARUM. 

uncriticised assumptions. It is reasoned, yet un- 
reflective. It builds up what is currently admitted 
to be knowledge, but it does not inquire what so- 
called knowledge is or is essentially worth. The 
philosophy which wholly depends on such assumed 
thought or knowledge has all their essential defects. 
It is merely an advance on special science, as special 
science itself is on ordinary knowledge, and ordinary 
knowledge on crude sensation. Along the whole 
line the mind never changes its attitude towards 
its objects. At the end its nature is just what it 
was at the beginning. Throughout what it brings 
with it is borrowed ordinary knowledge or positive 
science. The scientist often fancies that he is a 
man who takes nothing on trust when in reality he 
takes everything on trust, because he accepts 
without question or reservation thought itself as 
naturally truthful and its laws as valid. What- 
ever superficial scientists may suppose to the con- 
trary, the fact is that the entire procedure of 
science and of philosophy, in so far as it is simply 
a generalisation of science, is assumptive and dog- 
matic. Although often contrasted and opposed 
to faith it really rests on faith, and in the view 
of a serious and consistent scepticism must rest on 
blind faith. 

Thought may assume, however, and is bound to 
assume, a very different attitude towards itself and 



PHIL080PHY AS SCIENTIA SCIENTIARUM. 31 

towards its objects. It may pass and ought to 
pass from a believing to an inquiring, from a 
dogmatic to a critical stage. It may turn its 
attention and force from a study of the relations 
of the known to an examination of the conditions 
and guarantees of knowledge. 

In the second place, then, philosophy is bound 
to institute an investigation into the nature of 
knowledge itself 

All the special sciences aim merely at the exten- 
sion and acquisition of knowledge. They assume 
that there are things and truths to be known, but 
make no attempt to verify the assumption or even 
to understand what it implies. What are things 
apart from knowledge and in relation to knowledge ? 
Are things just what they appear to be, or not at 
all what they appear to be, or partly what they 
appear to be and partly not ? May all things not 
ultimately be thoughts or feelings, or even imagin- 
ations and illusions? If more or else than states 
or acts of mind, what more, what else? If they 
are affirmed to be existences, or substances, or 
realities, and the like, what precisely do such affirm- 
ations mean? What is truth? Is the assump- 
tion that we can' attain it well founded or a mere 
blind belief? If attainable, on what conditions and 
within what limits is it to be attained? What is 
knowledge? Is it possible? How is it possible? 



32 PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SCIENTIARUM. 

How can we separate between the knowable and 
the unknowable? What are we to think of such 
assertions as that knowledge is confined to experi- 
ence, or that spiritual things may be objects of 
faith but not of knowledge, or that metaphysical 
problems are incapable of solution? 

These are questions with which no special science 
deals, and which even philosophy as positive does not 
discuss. Positive philosophy is merely an advance 
on special science, as special science itself is on 
ordinary knowledge, and ordinary knowledge on 
crude and confused sensation. It accepts the 
sciences and endeavours by their combination and 
co-ordination to organise knowledge, but it leaves 
untouched the same questions as the special 
sciences, and consequently remains as assumptive 
and dogmatic as they are. For the special sciences 
and for a consistent positive philosophy, philo- 
sophical criticism and philosophical scepticism must 
be as if they were not. But they undoubtedly 
exist, and neither can nor ought to be ignored. 
Philosophy is bound not only to organise but to 
criticise whatever professes to be knowledge. It 
must not only survey knowledge as a whole and 
trace the relations of its parts, but it must satisfy 
itself as to its grounds and guarantees, and nearly 
corresponds to what has been designated by Kant 
critical philosophy. 



PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SCIENTIARUM. 33 

What may be called positive philosophy naturally 
prepares the way for critical philosophy. Kant 
will always be honoured as the man who first ade- 
quately realised the necessity under which philos- 
ophy lay to exercise its critical functions, and who 
gave the first general yet profound exposition of 
philosophy as a criticism of knowledge. He erred 
seriously, however, even in his conception of its 
problems, and still more seriously in his attempted 
solutions. Hence the cry of * Back to Kant ' which 
for a time resounded widely throughout Germany, 
and to a considerable extent, although compara- 
tively feebly, in Britain and America, cannot be 
justly regarded as having been wholly the voice of 
wisdom. 1 No one, however, has done so much for 
critical philosophy as Kant. Even his errors have 
in a wonderful measure proved more valuable than 
other men's truths. 

In the third place, philosophy requires to elabo- 
rate a theory of being and becoming in accordance 
with its views of the sciences and its criticism of 
knowledge. 

Philosophy as critical examines all the assump- 
tions on which philosophy as positive and the special 
sciences proceed. It is only through critical philo- 

1 See the criticism of Kant's criticism in Hegel's History of Philos- 
ophy, vol. iii. pp. 423-478 (E.T.) ; and the author's in Agnosticism, 
pp. 140-190. 

C 



34 PHILOSOPHY AS SCIBNTIA SCIBNTIARUM. 

sophy that thought can assure itself that what are 
called science and knowledge have anything to cor- 
respond to them, — that their supposition of real 
objects or objective realities is not a baseless illu- 
sion, — that sense and reason are not essentially 
antagonistic, and experience not inherently self- 
contradictory. This assurance it may conceivably 
fail to attain. It may, on the contrary, be forced 
either to the conclusion that nothing real exists, or 
that if anything real exists it cannot be known. 
In other words, its criticism of knowledge may lead 
to philosophical nihilism or to agnosticism. But it 
may also issue in the refutation of these hypotheses 
and the vindication of the beliefs which under- 
lie the special sciences, ordinary knowledge, and 
common life. It may warrant the conviction that 
objective reality is the necessary antecedent and 
universal correlative of the subjective activity in 
knowledge, and that, so far from being absolutely 
unknowable, it is continuously self-revealing even 
to our very limited minds. If this result, however, 
be reached, philosophy is manifestly bound to en- 
deavour to exhibit the nature of the ultimate reality 
or realities which the special sciences presuppose 
and in some measure reveal, but with which they 
cannot directly deal, first because they are special, 
and secondly because they are kinds of know- 
ledge, and logically anterior to the criticism of 



PHILOSOPHY AS SCI EN TI A SCIENTIARUM. 35 

knowledge. Philosophy in this phase — philosophy 
as the theory of being and becoming — is what 
has for very long been known as metaphysical 
philosophy. 

As such it cannot be satisfied with mere objec- 
tive appearances or subjective impressions. It must 
seek to penetrate farther, must seek after the un- 
seen and eternal, and strive if possible to attain 
some apprehension of ultimate reality, of absolute 
being, in Nature, Mind, or Deity. Metaphysics 
has sometimes been identified with Philosophy; 
but that is to make either the one term or the 
other useless. Obviously the latter term is the 
one best entitled to the wider signification. The 
former, even if considerably restricted, will still 
be found sufficiently comprehensive for any good 
purpose. It will appropriately include Ontology, 
the doctrine of being or reality as distinct from 
phenomenon, appearance, or illusion; Psychology, 
but only so far as regards the primary intuitions 
of reason and their corresponding immutable ob- 
jects; and Theology, but not further tJian as 
occupied with Godhead as the one absolute 
existence. To a large extent Psychology and 
Theology are independent of Metaphysics. 

The difficulty of defining Metaphysics is well 
known. I prefer to regard it not as a science 
but as a function of philosophy, although I do 



36 PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SCIENTIAEUM. 

not see any serious objection to such a definition 
of it as, say, Trendelenburg's, — "the science 
which considers what is universal in the objects 
of all the sciences" ; and still less to that of 
Prof. Fraser, — "the knowledge of being in its 
universal principles." Either knowledge or phil- 
osophy seems to me a better generic term for 
Metaphysics than science. The jocular definition 
even given of it by De Morgan is decidedly 
suggestive, — "The science to which ignorance goes 
to learn its knowledge, and knowledge to learn 
its ignorance. On which all men agree that it is 
the key, but no two upon how it is to be put 
into the lock." 

The metaphysical function of philosophy is a 
most important one. Although it may not be 
exact science, such science has owed a great deal 
to it. It has engrossed the attention and 
energies of many of the world's greatest thinkers. 
Socrates by his questionings, Plato by his dialogues 
and dialectic, and Aristotle by the work called 
(not by himself, however) 'Metaphysics/ were 
among the first clearly to show what it meant 
and should aim at accomplishing. The most re- 
nowned oriental, medieval, and modern philosophers 
have been eminent metaphysicians, and their repu- 
tations as philosophers have been largely owing to 
their having been wise enough not to despise 



PHILOSOPHY A3 SCIENTIA SCIENTIARUM. 37 

Metaphysics' rightly understood. There is not 
the slightest likelihood of ' Metaphysics ' becoming 
extinct. It will be despised only by the foolish 
or by those who are ignorant of what it means. 
No highly thoughtful man can fail to be some- 
what of a metaphysical cast of mind. 

In the fourth place, philosophy ought to forecast, 
as far as it can, the course of things, — the future 
of the world and life, of humanity and science, — 
and to determine what the worth of enjoyment is, 
and of truth, beauty, virtue, and piety, in relation 
to one another, and to the great final end of 
existence. 

Philosophy as a science of the sciences, as an 
inquiry into the nature and limits of knowledge, 
and as a doctrine of being and becoming, — or, in 
other words, philosophy as positive, critical, and 
metaphysical, — is theoretical philosophy in its three 
stages, and the whole of theoretical philosophy; 
but not the whole of philosophy, because although 
philosophy be fundamentally and predominantly 
theoretical, a merely theoretical philosophy must 
be essentially incomplete. Practical applicability 
is a necessary consequence of theoretical accuracy. 
The true theory of the relations of the sciences, 
of the conditions of knowledge, and of the nature 
of existence and causation, must be also the only 
true basis of doctrine as to the ends and issues, 



38 PHILOSOPHY A3 SCI EN TI A SCIENTIARUM. 

the purposes and destinies of the beings which con- 
stitute the universe. Whither tends the physical 
world ? What is the chief end of man ? To what 
goal is society moving? Is life worth living? Is 
optimism or pessimism or an intermediate hy- 
pothesis the legitimate conception of existence? 
Questions like these can only be answered aright 
in connection with a general theory of final causes 
such as a comprehensive and profound philosophy 
alone can provide. The answers given to them 
even by the most comprehensive and profound 
philosophy of the present age, and of many ages 
to come, may be far from distinct and certain, and 
yet may gradually approximate to the full truth as 
time advances and knowledge increases. Philo- 
sophy, when engaged in the study of these ques- 
tions and seeking to be helpful in the guidance of 
active life, may be appropriately entitled practical 
philosophy. 

The four regions of thought now indicated com- 
prise the entire domain of philosophy. Those who 
would successfully explore that vast domain should 
begin their investigations with its first region. As 
I have already indicated, philosophy as positive 
ought to precede philosophy whether critical or 
metaphysical or practical. Although the followers 
of Comte and the advocates of the so-called " scien- 
tific philosophy" err greatly in supposing that 



PHILOSOPHY A3 SCIKNTIA SCIBNTIARUM. 39 

philosophy is merely the synthesis and generalisa- 
tion of the positive or special sciences, they are 
perfectly right in maintaining that philosophy must 
be based on these sciences, and can only verify 
itself through accepting and conforming to their 
conclusions. Philosophy must base itself on the 
sciences even while searching for their bases. It 
may conceivably prove science to be illusory, but 
in doing so it must annihilate itself, as it can only 
establish its own claim to credence by first vindi- 
cating the truthfulness of the sciences and then 
appealing to their testimony. Thus philosophy as 
positive must precede philosophy as critical, meta- 
physical, and practical; and critical philosophy, 
metaphysical philosophy, and practical philosophy 
must submit to be attested by the conclusions of 
a positive philosophy which accepts the well-estab- 
lished results of any and every science. 

If the view just stated be approved we shall be 
freed from the danger of falling into either of two 
common and hurtful errors. The first is the identi- 
fication of philosophy with some special science or 
group of sciences. The narrow notion that one 
science belongs to philosophy and another not, that 
the mental sciences are philosophical and the physi- 
cal sciences non-philosophical, is still prevalent, but 
is essentially and intensely unphilosophical. There 
is no objection to using the terms science and philo- 



40 PHILOSOPHY A3 SCIENTIA 3CIENTIAEUM. 

sophy popularly, interchangeably, when no harm 
is likely to be done thereby ; but if we distinguish 
and delimit them there is but one view of philo- 
sophy which can justify itself either historically 
or logically, and it is that which regards it not 
as exclusive of any of the sciences, but as com- 
prehensive of them all. From this view it follows 
immediately, on the one hand, that no special 
science can claim to be philosophy as against any 
other special science, and, on the other hand, that 
no special science is excluded from having the 
closest connection with and interest in philo- 
sophy; that each special science, one may even 
say each special subject, has its philosophy; the 
philosophy of any subject as distinguished from 
the science of that subject being the view or theory 
of its relations to other things, to the universe of 
which it is a part, as distinguished from the view 
or theory of it as isolated or in itself. 

The other grave error to which our account of 
philosophy is directly opposed is that which would 
found it on common-sense, on ordinary knowledge, 
on untested and unanalysed consciousness. In pro- 
nouncing appeals to common-sense to be illegitimate, 
I take common-sense in its ordinary acceptation, and 
censure in no degree appeals to those so-called prin- 
ciples of common-sense which are simply the ulti- 
mate conditions of thought as adequately ascertained 



PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SCIENTIARUM. 41 

by psychological analysis. What is alone objection- 
able is that 'the science of the sciences' should 
appeal from science to any lower tribunal. Science 
is more definite and better grounded than ordinary 
knowledge ; nearer the perfect form of human know- 
ledge ; such knowledge in its completest and purest 
state. Therefore whenever science can be had it is 
with science that philosophy should have to do, and 
by science that it must be tried and judged. Each 
science reduces to order, each science develops to 
perfection or approximate perfection so much ordin- 
ary knowledge, and philosophy has to avail itself of 
the achievements of the separate sciences. Hence 
an important reduction, an important simplification, 
of its labour. As far as possible it has to do not 
directly with the comparative chaos of common 
knowledge, but with the separate systems of order 
which constitute the special sciences. Wherever it 
can do better it ought never to appeal from the 
higher to the lower tribunal, — from Philip sober to 
Philip drunk. 



III. 



Some observations on the various kinds or stages 
of knowledge still seem to be called for. To appre- 
hend aright the nature of one phase or species of 
knowledge acquaintance with that of others is in- 



42 PHIL080PHY AS SCIENTIA SCIENTIARUM. 

dispensable. Yet it has long been, and still is, 
common to assume that knowledge is only three- 
fold, although the assumption is very erroneous, and 
has given rise to various false inferences. There are 
many stages and kinds of knowledge, and so im- 
portant a fact should not be overlooked or the vast 
significance of it fail to be realised as fully as 
possible. Yet there are even scientists and philo- 
sophers who treat of ordinary human knowledge as 
if it were the primary source and oldest form of 
knowledge. Of course that is a very great error, 
one which assumes that there was no animal in- 
telligence or knowledge on earth before mankind 
appeared on its surface, and that the deepest roots of 
consciousness and thought were brought into the 
world with the advent of palaeolithic man or a 
primeval Adam. There is not only no warrant for 
the assumption, but absolutely conclusive evidence 
to the contrary. 

There was animal consciousness on earth for in- 
calculable ages before the genus homo appeared on 
it. Human psychology instead of being the whole 
of psychology is a very small portion of it. There 
is a psychology possible of far vaster extent, — a 
comparative psychology the aim of which should be 
comprehensive enough to take account of all kinds 
of creatures that have lived, suffered, and died 
on earth, and capable of realising aright what 



PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA 8CIENTIARUM. 43 

their experiences, their inner as well as outer his- 
tories, have been. Its task may be a very difficult 
one, but it cannot be reasonably held to be an im- 
possible one. Why not ? Just because man has in 
his own inmost nature the key to all animal con- 
sciousness. In every state of consciousness he has 
what are called feeling, knowing, and willing, or, in 
other words, sensation, cognition, and volition. But 
so has every animal, even the least and meanest. 
The three elements of consciousness are inseparable 
alike in man and beast, and hence the former may 
by a judiciously directed study of the latter acquire 
a very considerable amount of knowledge of the 
actions, meanings, and experiences of animals of 
every kind; and at every stage of their existence. 
The course of the history of knowledge on earth 
began apparently with the origination of animal life 
on earth, although there are some scientists who be- 
lieve that it began earlier, and that sentiency and 
consciousness had their roots even in the vegetable 
kingdom. In proof they have pointed to facts 
traceable throughout the vegetable kingdom and to 
adaptations between certain plants and their physi- 
cal surroundings analogous to those that take place 
in consequence of the repetition of animal actions 
and the formation even of human habits. Among 
the most relevant and best known of such facts are 
the curious arrangement and action of the leaves in 



44 PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SCIENTIARUM. 

the pitcher-plant; the rapid and peculiar motion which 
makes* the Dionaea muscipula an efficient fly-trap ; 
what Darwin calls the ' nice sense ' of the Mimosa ; 
and the elongation and contraction of the stalk of 
the Vallisneria according as the waters in which it 
grows rise or fall. But however analogous or akin 
to animal actions such movements may appear, no 
one has as yet proved them to be of the same 
nature, whereas it is certain that knowledge began 
wherever even the lowest animal life began. All 
animals have intelligence, and many of them an 
amazing intelligence. Yet not a few attempts have 
been made to explain away their intelligence; and to 
represent their actions as merely automatic, as due 
to the mechanical play of bodily organs, or to irrit- 
ability, or to the immediate and sole operations of 
deity, or to instinct undefined. 

It was a curious fact that so late as the year 
1874-75 such men as Prof. Huxley (in The Fort- 
nightly Review), and Dr Carpenter, Mr Mivart, and 
the late Duke of Argyll (in The Contemporary 
Review), should have been discussing the question, 
Whether or not animals are automata? Certainly 
if animals are automata and their actions automatic 
so are men and their actions. 1 Man and beasts are 
alike machines in that they are alike influenced by 

1 See Janet's Final Causes (E.T.), Bk. I. c. v., Mechanism and 
Finality, pp. 137-178. 



PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SCIENTIARUM. 45 

their physical organisation and alike different from 
machines in that they are alike endowed with sen- 
tiency, appetite, desire, and activity. Sir Isaac 
Newton, Addison, Bonnet, and others have spoken 
of the instinctive actions of animals as immediate 
operations of Deity. They have represented the 
phenomena of so-called instinct as ' the direct mani- 
festations of the Divine energy in animals/ as * to 
be explained by the continued and universal pres- 
ence of a living intelligent Spirit,' and ' the body 
of an insect as but a curtain hiding the operations 
of the Supreme Artist/ — a view which implies 
that * God is the soul of brutes/ — an opinion far 
from peculiarly pious, — a theory which, if con- 
sistently carried out, would reduce all nervous 
actions and all mental processes both in man 
and beasts to divine operations, and land us in 
complete pantheism. 

Others have represented the study of animal mind 
as impracticable and futile, on the grounds that we 
are either (1) not conscious of what takes place in 
animal mind or (2) that animal consciousness is 
merely a quasi -consciousness. Both reasons are 
exceedingly weak. If we can know only the mental 
states of which we are self-conscious it is not merely 
the minds of beasts that we must remain ignorant 
of, but every human mind except our own, and also 
the Divine mind, for all those minds are alike un- 



46 PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SCIENTIARUM. 

known to us except through their self-manifesta- 
tions to us. 

As inconclusive is it to assert that animal con- 
sciousness cannot be apprehended and interpreted 
by us because it is only quasi-consciousness. The 
reply to that is obvious. How can what is asserted 
as known be known by those who assert it? To 
be entitled to say what they do say they must 
have already done what they declare cannot be 
done ; must have interpreted animal conscious- 
ness and - ascertained what it is before they can 
rationally believe or pronounce it to be anything — 
or even quasi anything — else. Unless they know 
what it is, how do they know that it is not such 
consciousness as they themselves possess, but a 
mysterious tertium quid between that conscious- 
ness and unconsciousness. As to the second reason 
referred to, a quasi-consciousness is an absurdity. 
To call the pain which an animal gives evidence of 
suffering quasi-pain should be recognised by every 
sane person as an abuse of language. There is no 
medium, tertium quid, or quasi in such a case. 
There is either pain or not pain, sensation or non- 
sensation, knowledge or ignorance. 

Seeing that consciousness and knowledge belong 
to all creatures in the animal kingdom, man as 
the earthly head of that kingdom is not only self- 
conscious and self-cognitive but capable of under- 



PHILOSOPHY AS SOIENTIA SCIENTIARUM. 47 

standing what are the sentiency and knowledge 
of the countless active beings which Zoology distri- 
butes into its multitudinous divisions, — its types, 
classes, orders, sub-orders, and families. The psy- 
chical life and consciousness of all mere animals is 
much simpler and more limited than that of man, 
and may naturally be found, in consequence, to be 
much more easily understood. That animal intelli- 
gence is, as a whole, however, a lower stage of 
intelligence than the human, and that in every 
animal species the variation is greater than in the 
human, must be admitted, and the main reason for 
such being the case seems obviously to be that the 
animal mind is much more dependent on the bodily 
organism than the human mind is on the human 
body. The former is in comparison much less free. 
Whereas the manifestations of knowledge in animals 
are often seemingly automatic, in man they are, in 
comparison, very exceptionally so. Were it other- 
wise, the achievements of many species of animals 
would be far more extraordinary than those of a 
similar character performed by man. Some of the 
smallest species of animals display the largest 
amount of intelligence. The elephant is sagacious 
within certain limits, and in comparison with the 
rhinoceros or hippopotamus, but its knowledge is 
far less wonderful and exact than the knowledge 
of ants, bees, and beavers. Ants are not only cap- 



48 PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SCIENTIARUM. 

able of giving good lessons to sluggards but they 
display a marvellous knowledge in an architecture 
of their own, the importance of social organisation, 
and how to conduct war with vast numbers. Bees 
in the construction of the cells of their honeycombs 
not only solved an economic problem of the utmost 
practical importance to them, but which was also so 
difficult a problem of the higher mathematics that a 
completely satisfactory solution was first given by 
Colin Maclaurin in the Transactions of the Royal 
Society of London. The naturalists who have made 
a special study of the operations and habits of 
beavers are agreed as to their extraordinary intelli- 
gence. In one well-authenticated case these crea- 
tures have been proved to have, for generation after 
generation during at least a thousand years, con- 
structed their lodges, dams, and canals, so as to 
have at length changed the entire configuration of 
the region in which they had operated. 

The whole animal world is participant in know- 
ledge. Every kind of living creature has some 
measure of intelligence, sentiency, and self-activity. 
Whence come they? Whence has every living 
creature its share of them ? Surely not from mere 
matter in any form, nor from the creatures them- 
selves by any self-creative power, but only from an 
eternal self-existent Intelligence, an Intelligence to 
which no origin or limit can be assigned, an infinite 



PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SCIENTIARUM. 49 

and ever-living Being creative and comprehensive of 
all that knows and all that is known. Apparently 
there were many and long ages before there was any 
life and intelligence on earth ; but conceivably also 
the sources of consciousness and knowledge may 
have been present in the cosmic ether before our 
world became a globe differentiated from all other 
worlds. Nor is it entirely certain, perhaps, that 
vegetable and animal vitality may not have had in 
an incalculably remote age on earth their origins in 
the same protoplasmic substance. What is alone 
indubitable is that conscious life has had an exceed- 
ingly long history on earth. 

That it was preceded by a vastly long history 
of entirely dead matter does not seem to have 
been adequately proved either in the affirmative 
or negative. Even a molecule of matter would 
appear to have a history in or behind which alike 
the chemist and biologist, geologist and palaeon- 
tologist, have failed entirely to decipher. No 
educated person, however, thanks to the labours of 
those scientists, can now fail to believe that the 
history of animal life and intelligence has already 
been one of amazing and incalculable length, as 
well as vast breadth, and that from its first known 
appearance until the present time it has been a 
history of unbroken continuity the development 
of which can be traced as plainly as the history 

D 



50 PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SOIBNTIARUM. 

of any individual It has passed through many 
epochs and phases, every epoch having its own 
physiognomy and every phase of every epoch having 
presented some variation, but there has nowhere 
been complete separation of the stages or radical 
difference between the species of animals that have 
lived and worked, enjoyed and suffered in those 
stages. Absolutely new and original species, how- 
ever, have been nowhere discovered. From the 
earliest time animal nature has had general features 
in common with those of to-day. It is impossible 
to draw an absolute limit between the beings that 
have existed before us and those that are living 
around us. 

Our animal world is not distinct from the fossil 
world, but rests on it and is the continuation of it 
at almost every point. The two in alliance have 
had a series and history of the stages which are 
so many periods of progress alike in the general 
history of the animal world and in the special 
history of mankind. And hence there has been 
in the main a continuous growth of animal and 
human intelligence and knowledge towards develop- 
ment and improvement. The numbers of animals and 
men have been increased. There has been greater 
differentiation alike of their physical and mental 
organisation. There has likewise been progress as 
regards sensibility, intelligence, and activity — e.g., 



PHILOSOPHY AS SCIBNTIA SCIENTIARUM. 51 

improvement in sight, hearing, smell, affectionate 
and social sentiments, a higher development of the 
nervous system, and more combination and co- 
operation. 

One has a temptation to dwell on so interesting 
a subject, but I must not yield to it, as it has been 
in recent times dwelt on by many distinguished 
scientists. The study of animal mind had been 
inaugurated by Aristotle's History of Animals, yet 
during the last fifty or sixty years it will scarcely 
be questioned to have been more carefully and 
fruitfully cultivated than all those which had pre- 
ceded them. Comparative Psychology is mainly 
the creation of the present age, during which there 
has, perhaps, been no more interesting scientific 
achievement. It has immensely extended the 
sphere of psychological study. Among those who 
deserve most credit for that result have been Bingley, 
Btichner, Darwin, Gaudry, Houzeau, Huber, Jesse, 
Lubbock, Perty, Romanes, Semper, and Wundt 
They are all authors of most instructive and easily 
procurable works. 

Of human knowledge there are universally re- 
cognised to be three kinds or stages — viz., ordinary, 
scientific, and philosophic knowledge. Ordinary 
knowledge is the kind of knowledge common to 
all sane men but also such knowledge as is often 



52 PHILOSOPHY AS 8CIENTIA SCIENTIARUM. 

extremely indistinct, confused, and superficial. It 
is not strictly definable and generally very vague 
as to its contents. The nature of it is common not 
to men only but to all animals. It is distinguishable 
from science by its lack of precision and exactness 
and from philosophy by its lack of comprehensiveness 
and profundity. Even as knowledge of particular 
objects and limited ends indeed it implies universal 
principles and rational intuitions but is not con- 
sciously and distinctly aware of them. Only in the 
scientific and philosophical stages do they come 
clearly to light. Yet ordinary knowledge is a 
knowledge by no means to be despised. A large 
portion of it is probably of more value than much 
which is called science and believed in as such. 
Although less exact than science it is often less 
capable of being dispensed with. A human world 
composed exclusively of scientific experts might 
very possibly, and not very improbably, be not 
better but worse than one like the present com- 
posed for the most part of merely ordinarily 
intelligent men. There is a vast amount of 
ordinary knowledge which is more helpful and of 
more real human interest than there is of science. 
All the roots of scientific thinking are already in 
ordinary knowledge. Compared with ordinary 
thought the amount of scientific thought is very 
limited. 



PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SOIBNTIARUM. 53 

Scientific knowledge is, nevertheless, rightly 
regarded as on the whole a higher stage of know- 
ledge than non-scientific or ordinary knowledge. It 
is a knowledge of more than mere facts or common 
observations and experiences, including as it does 
a search for the reasons and causes of things as well 
as of mere perceptions of them, or, in Greek 
phraseology, not merely the art but also the Sioti 
of phenomena. And, further, all scientific know- 
ledge is knowledge of a specific kind, and differ- 
entiated from knowledge not of that kind. Each 
science has a sphere of its own, and is not to be 
confounded with ununified and indeterminate know- 
ledge. The scientist is a specialist, and as such one 
who keeps within a province peculiarly his own, 
and distinguishes it from other provinces, although 
if a wise man he will look beyond it and take note 
of what other scientists are doing in contiguous 
departments. The methods appropriate to the 
several sciences must vary with their objects. 
Still less, of course, is scientific knowledge to be 
identified with mere belief, or with mere art and 
practice, than with ordinary knowledge. To collect 
facts, to analyse material objects and mental states, 
to distinguish between semblance and reality, to 
discover and formulate laws of sequence, to bring 
to light the conditions of order and organisation 
alike in the physical and spiritual worlds, are what 



54 PHILOSOPHY AS SCIBNTIA SOIKNTIARUM. 

the sciences have to accomplish, each in its own 
province. 

Science is often, but not always, what had been 
merely ordinary knowledge in an advanced and 
improved stage. It is not always so because when 
sciences are thoroughly established they are often 
capable of evolution from within so as to yield 
vast accessions to knowledge such as have never 
existed except in scientific form. Mathematics is 
constantly thus extending itself into regions where 
unscientific intellect has never been, and conse- 
quently can predict effects which have never been 
observed, and may be carried to developments far 
beyond the reach of experiments. But in general 
science issues out of ordinary knowledge, and that 
knowledge may in every case be regarded as a 
step towards scientific knowledge, — as a humbler 
stage always, a prior stage generally of the same 
movement or process. Science rises superior to 
ordinary knowledge in being both more general 
and more definite. More general inasmuch as it 
regards things not as isolated and individual but 
as included under some law, as terms of some fixed 
relation, of coexistence, or succession; and more 
definite as implying a recognition of the exact re- 
lation in which one fact stands to another, whereas 
ordinary knowledge in its recognition of connection 
between facts is merely of some sort of connection. 



PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SOLKNTIARUM. 55 

In a general way philosophic knowledge may 
reasonably be held to be the highest stage and 
most comprehensive kind of human knowledge, 
but only when it strives with a fair measure of 
success to realise the ideal at which it aims. All 
that assumes to be philosophy is not to be taken 
simply on its own authority. Much of it has 
been found to be instead of perfect knowledge 
pretentious nonsense. But genuine philosophy is 
worthy of all the praise which has been bestowed 
upon it. Wherever there has been active and 
earnest thinking, wherever the arts have flourished, 
wherever the sciences have prospered, wherever 
civilisation has spread, there philosophy can be 
shown to have been at work. The term itself 
and the history of it have been suggestive and 
instructive as to what it has meant and ought 
to mean. It was as "the love of wisdom," and 
not as the acquisition of mere knowledge, that it 
was called into existence, and the Pythagoreans 
and Platonists continued to regard "the yearning 
after divine wisdom" as what was properly dis- 
tinctive of it. Cicero spoke of it as " the science 
of divine and human things and of the causes 
in which they are contained." Descartes changed, 
and contributed to modernise, the conception of 
it, by representing it as "the pursuit of the 
perfect knowledge of all things that men can 



56 PHILOSOPHY A8 SCIENTIA SCIENTIARUM. 

know, deduced from first principles." Kant de- 
scribed it as "the science of the relations of all 
knowledge to the essential ends of human reason." 
Lotze's definition of it (in his Grundziige der 
Logik, § 83) is "an effort to import unity and 
connectedness into the scattered doctrines of cul- 
tured thought, to follow each of these directions 
into its assumptions and into its consequences, 
to combine them together, to remove their con- 
tradictions, and to form out of them a compre- 
hensive view of the world; mainly, however, to 
subject the ideas which science and life regard 
as principles to a special scrutiny in order to 
determine the limits of their validity." Even 
those few definitions may suffice to show what 
has been the course of thought as to the nature 
of philosophy. It has been a long course and 
one never entirely interrupted. Philosophy has 
always preceded what we would call science. Wher- 
ever there is earnest human thought as to truth 
and error, good and evil, right and wrong, there is 
something of the nature of philosophy, and as 
such it aspires to be coextensive with human 
knowledge, claims the right of criticising and 
testing all opinions, and hesitates not to raise 
and try to answer the most difficult and per- 
plexing yet engrossing and important questions 
which can come before the human mind. Hence 



PHILOSOPHY AS 8CIENTIA 8CIENTIARUM. 57 

philosophy is rightly, and almost universally, 
regarded as the last and highest stage of human 
intelligence. 

Philosophy, in order to be as comprehensive as 
it ought, has to deal as its subject with the entire 
intelligible universe, the three final existences of 
which are God, the world, and self. Its ways or 
modes of manifestation and action are : — 
1°, Positive or Phenomenological ; 2°, Critical or 
Epistemological ; 3°, Metaphysical or Theoretical; 
and 4°, Practical ; or, it may suffice to say simply 
the positive, the critical, the metaphysical, and 
the practical. 

Philosophy as universal science has, in the first 
place, to deal in a comprehensive and general way 
with what all the special positive sciences deal with 
in a sectional way. It has to seek to attain to a 
knowledge of the unity, self-consistency, and har- 
mony of the teachings of these separate sciences, 
and to a knowledge of what the universe is accord- 
ing to their collective testimony. Philosophy as 
thus a synthesis of the positive sciences is Positive 
Philosophy. As such it deals only with phenomena, 
appearances, particular experiences, — with what the 
ordinary man and the positivist scientist accept as 
alone facts. According to Comte and the adherents 
of all the positivist schools there is no other philo- 
sophy than such positive philosophy. In that they 



58 PHILOSOPHY AS SCIBNTIA 8CIENTIARUM. 

err, but they axe in no way mistaken io maintain- 
ing that there is a positive philosophy, and that it 
is of primary and fundamental importance. They 
are only mistaken in supposing that philosophy can 
rationally stop where they would have it to do. 

Philosophy should be critical as well as positive. 
A merely positive philosophy must be a very 
imperfect philosophy. Philosophy as positive is 
far from an adequate ideal of philosophy. Even 
scientific thought is not necessarily self-criticising 
thought; on the contrary, mere scientific thought, 
however rigid and methodical, is essentially dog- 
matic thought, — reasoned yet unreflective thought. 
It builds up what is admitted to be knowledge, but 
it does not inquire what so-called knowledge is or 
is essentially worth. The mere scientist often 
fancies that he is a man who takes nothing on 
trust, when, in reality, he is taking everything 
on trust, because he accepts without question or 
reservation thought itself as naturally truthful, and 
its laws as valid. Whatever superficial scientists 
may suppose to the contrary, the fact is that the 
entire procedure of science, and of philosophy in 
so far as it is merely a generalisation of science, is 
assumptive and dogmatic. The science which is so 
often contrasted and opposed to faith by sceptics is 
frequently implicit faith, and in the view of a serious 
and consistent scepticism must be deemed a blind 



PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SCIBKTIARUM. 59 

faith. Thought may assume, however, and is even 
bound to assume, a very different attitude towards 
itself and its own objects ; not only may but ought 
to pass from a believing to an inquiring, from a 
dogmatic to a critical stage, from a study merely v 
of the superficial and apparent in knowledge to an 
examination of the conditions and guarantees of 
knowledge. Philosophy, in a word, has not only 
to accumulate what passes for knowledge in the 
opinion of positivists, but must assure itself as to 
the solidity of its own foundations. As critical it 
is occupied with a fundamental and universal 
problem, the problem as to the possibility and 
reality of knowledge of every kind, if philosophy 
is not to end in nihilism or agnosticism. It is 
essentially epistemology (inclusive of what is philo- 
sophical in logic and methodology). 

Philosophy, besides being positive and critical, 
should also be metaphysical (systematical or theo- 
retical). The criticism of what passes for know- 
ledge may lead only to a negative or sceptical 
result, either to philosophical nihilism or agnos- 
ticism. Were it to be successful, however, all so- 
called science must be but an inevitable and 
ineradicable illusion, and all so-called knowledge 
at bottom no knowledge, or the knowledge of 
nothing. In that case philosophy might be best 
defined as a demonstration of the vanity of 



60 PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SCIENTIARUM. 

thought. While, however, its criticism of know- 
ledge may conceivably lead to philosophical nihilism 
or agnosticism, it may also, on the contrary, issue 
in the refutation of them and the vindication of the 
beliefs which underlie the special sciences, ordinary 
knowledge, and common life. In other words, it 
may warrant the conviction that objective reality 
is the necessary antecedent and universal correlative 
of the subjective activity in knowledge, and so far 
from being absolutely unknowable is continuously 
revealing itself, even to our very limited minds. 
But if that result be reached, philosophy is mani- 
festly bound to exhibit the nature of the ultimate 
which the special sciences presuppose and so far 
manifest, but with which they cannot competently 
deal — first, because they are special, and, secondly, 
because they are logically anterior to the criticism of 
knowledge. Philosophy in that phase has for very 
long been known as metaphysical or ontological 
philosophy. It has also been often termed 
systematic, theoretic, or speculative. Of course, 
philosophy as metaphysical has to determine 
whether or not there is God, the ground and 
source of all being, the reason of all existences and 
events, and cannot escape the necessity of being 
either theistic or antitheistic. It has to deal with 
all dogmatic metaphysical theories, and all such 
theories must be either theistic or anti - theistic. 



PHILOSOPHY AS 8CIENTIA SCIENTIARUM. 61 

Hence it cannot itself escape the necessity of being 
either theistic or anti-theistic. If the former be 
arrived at, it is its obvious duty to tell us what it 
can of God, of the world in relation to God, of man 
in relation to God, of providence and theodicy, of 
revelation and its media, of the destination of man- 
kind and the consummation of things, of the aims, 
ideals, spheres of action of the religious life, and the 
like. A theistic metaphysical philosophy is bound 
in self-consistency to exhibit the knowledge of God 
as the alone absolute and all-comprehensive know- 
ledge, — the idea of ideas in metaphysical language, 
— and as inclusive of all the categories of being and 
thought in their perfection. A correct doctrine of 
the nature and function of the categories in thought 
shows what is meant by knowing God as the abso- 
lute, why it is erroneous to say that we cannot 
know God, seeing that we can only know the 
relative or the phenomenal, and the categories are 
only valid for experience. In reality, all progress 
in speculation, in science, in moral experience, and 
in spiritual life, promotes progress in knowledge of 
God. 

Philosophy as a scheme of the sciences, as an 
inquiry into the nature and limits of knowledge, 
and as a doctrine of being and becoming, — or, in 
other words, philosophy as positive, critical, and 
metaphysical, — is theoretical philosophy in its three 



62 PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SCIENTIARUM. 

stages, and the whole of theoretical philosophy. It 
is not the whole of philosophy, however, because 
although philosophy be fundamentally and predomi- 
nantly theoretical, a merely theoretical philosophy 
must be essentially incomplete. Practical applic- 
ability is a necessary consequence of theoretical 
accuracy. The true theory of the relations of the 
sciences, of the conditions of knowledge, and of the 
nature of existence and causation must be also the 
only true basis of doctrine as to the ends and issues, 
the purposes and destinies, of the beings which con- 
stitute the universe. Whither tends the physical 
world ? What is the chief end of man ? To what 
goal is society moving ? Is life worth living ? Is 
optimism or pessimism or an intermediate hypo- 
thesis the legitimate conception of existence ? Ques- 
tions like these can be answered aright only in con- 
nection with a general theory of final causes such 
as a comprehensive and profound philosophy can 
alone provide. The answers given to them even 
by the most comprehensive and profound philos- 
ophy of the present age, and of many ages to come, 
may be far from distinct and certain, and yet may 
gradually approximate to the full truth as time 
advances and knowledge increases. Philosophy 
when engaged in the study of these questions and 
seeking to be helpful in the guidance of active life 
may be appropriately entitled practical philosophy. 



PHILOSOPHY AS SCIENTIA SCIENTIARUM. 63 

Philosophy may not unreasonably present a claim 
to be regarded as the highest and most comprehen- 
sive kind of all human knowledge but certainly not 
of all knowledge. There is an infinitely vaster and 
more perfect knowledge than any to which man or 
any other or even all created beings can pretend to 
possess. There is a knowledge which we are very 
apt to ignore although all other knowledge in the 
universe springs from it and is closely connected 
with it. In other words, there are not merely ordi- 
nary and human knowledge, science, and philos- 
ophy, but omniscience, — divine intelligence and 
wisdom, — an all - comprehensive, perfect, and in- 
finite knowledge. Nothing can be hid from God. 
All is perfectly known to Him in the past, present, 
and future, from the highest to the lowest, and 
from the least to the greatest. He has all the 
perfections of knowledge in himself and also knows 
all that there is to know from without. Co-exten- 
sive with omniscience is omnipotence. They are 
indissolubly united. The former is not inactive 
nor the latter unenlightened. More need not here 
be said. The subject has been treated of in every 
comprehensive system of theology. 



A HISTORY OF CLASSIFICATIONS 
OF THE SCIENCES 



E 



A HISTORY OF CLASSIFICATIONS 
OF THE SCIENCES. 



rpHE first problem with which philosophy, alike 
as scientia sdentiarum and as positive phil- 
osophy, should deal seems to be how may the 
sciences be rationally arranged and classified. 
Unless it be so far accomplished obviously no 
attempt at the organisation of either knowledge 
or science can be successful. Philosophers have 
always felt, more or less distinctly, that such must 
be the case. They have never shown themselves 
wholly unconscious that they ought to aim at the 
organisation of knowledge. On the contrary, they 
have made many endeavours to realise that aim, and 
have always recognised that the first step or stage 
to the organisation required is some form of classifi- 
cation. From the time of Plato to the present day 
there has been a continuous series of attempts to 
classify the sciences. An historical and critical 
account of them can hardly fail to be useful, even 



68 PLATONIC SCHEME OF 

although none of them may have been completely 
successful. Indeed, no scheme of the sciences can 
be final and perfect so long as new sciences remain 
to be formed. On the other hand, few have been 
entirely worthless, and some may fairly be held to 
have been of much value. A study of them is 
indispensable at least to those who would improve 
on them. It is always helpful towards knowing 
how a thing ought to be done to consider how it 
has been done. Thus only can all the points of 
view, principles, and methods which require to be 
considered in connection with any difficult problem 
be brought distinctly before us. 



L FKOM PLATO TO THE KENAISSANCB. 

Platonic Plato was, perhaps, the first who sought to give a 
systematic distribution of knowledge. We must be 
careful not to confound with that distribution so- 
called divisions of his philosophy. Of its very 
nature his philosophy will not divide. Those who 
have divided it, like Marbach into general and 
applied, or, like Krug into theoretical and practical, 
have overlooked the fact, which numerous passages 
might be brought to substantiate, that, in the eyes 
of Plato, philosophy was an essentially practical 
spiritual process. It was not theory or practice, 



CLASSIFICATION OF THE SCIENCES. 69 

science or life, nor even theory applied to practice, 
science applied to life, but both in one — the striving 
of the soul to purify and ennoble itself, to make 
itself all beautiful within. There is no right under- 
standing of the philosophy of Plato possible if we 
forget that he regarded it as primarily a process, 
the true life of the spirit, the soul making of itself 
a divine poem, the highest music. It is equally 
incorrect to divide the Platonic philosophy, as Van 
Heusde has done, into a philosophy of the true, 
of the beautiful, and of the good. That is an 
altogether modern mode of dividing philosophy, 
and quite contrary to the spirit of Platonism. 
Philosophy was, according to Plato, not only 
essentially practical, but also essentially one, and 
one because all ideas lead up to the idea of the 
good. 

The division of philosophy most commonly 
attributed to him, however, is that into dialectics, 
physics, and ethics. But although Schwegler, 
Zeller, Ferrier, Ueberweg, Erdmann, and many 
others, have adopted it as substantially warranted, 
it can exhibit no valid claims. It is admitted that 
Plato nowhere distinctly states it. The very names 
physics and ethics are unknown to him, and dia- 
lectics is with him not a part of philosophy, but 
the whole of philosophy. The way in which he 
came to be credited with the division is apparent 



70 PLATONIC SCHEME OF 

from what Sextus Empiricus, who flourished about 
the beginning of the third century, says on the 
subject: "Of those who divide philosophy into 
physics, ethics, and logic, Plato is virtually the 
originator (Swa/xei oLpxvyo*)* having discoursed on 
many physical, many ethical, and not a few logical 
questions." * The latter clause is here obviously the 
explanation and reason of the former. It is because 
Plato has discoursed much on physical matters, 
much on ethical matters, and not a little on logic 
that he is affirmed to have been virtually the author 
of the threefold division of philosophy which was 
afterwards widely prevalent. There is, in fact, no 
other ground on which it can be carried up to Plato 
with any plausibility, and this ground is quite 
insufficient. That Plato wrote on all these three 
subjects cannot in any degree warrant us to call 
him even the virtual originator of the distribution. 
It was scarcely possible that Plato, or any other 
person, should write much on philosophy without 
handling to some extent both physics and ethics, 
and wholly impossible to handle them without 
keeping them in some measure apart, but that was 
a very different thing from making physics and 
ethics distinct parts of philosophy, co-ordinate with 
each other and with dialectics. That Plato certainly 
did not. There is no dialogue of Plato exclusively 

1 Adv. Math., vii. 16. 



CLASSIFICATION OF THE SCIENCES. 71 

dialectical, and no dialogue from which dialectics is 
excluded. Physical, ethical, and all other inquiries 
are only included in his philosophy in so far as they 
are dialectical, and his dialectics exists only as deal- 
ing with the idealities of nature and spirit. Plato 
knows nothing of a logic which has a province of 
its own apart from all definite ideal contents. It 
is vain to try to classify his writings as dialectical, 
physical, and ethical. 

Plato's distribution of knowledge is one involved 
in his very theory of knowledge. It has been 
discussed so often that I shall treat of it as briefly 
as possible, and only because I must. According to 
Plato, then, two worlds lie before the vision of man, 
—a visible world and an intelligible world. Each of 
these worlds, in its turn, divides into two. Thus 
the visible world is made up either of things or of 
images of things. The former are the rocks, trees, 
animals, &c. ; the latter are the shadows and reflec- 
tions which they throw off, — such shadows and 
reflections as may be seen in water or in a mirror. 
All the objects of the visible world are discerned 
only through sense (aZcrfycris), but sense in contact 
with things generates belief (moris), while in con- 
tact with images (cikwcs) it generates merely con- 
jecture (eiKaaia). Belief and conjecture are but a 
higher and lower form of opinion (Sofa). Belief 
differs from conjecture; views based on things are 



72 PLATONIC 8CHEME OF 

not to be confounded with views based on mere 
shadows, and have a greater worth and usefulness ; 
but in no form can the informations of sense give 
us truth or be entitled to the name of knowledge. 

There is, however, an intelligible world, with 
objects which reason apprehends and not sense. 
These objects are likewise divisible into two classes, 
— conceptions and ideas. Conceptions are on the 
lower level, and the mind reaches them by the help 
of certain objects of sense which are a sort of images 
of them. The mathematical sciences are conversant 
with them, and in these sciences we make use of 
visible figures, and motions, and audible sounds, but 
only to help us to the comprehension of forms, pro- 
perties, and ratios, which intellect alone can grasp. 
They are five in number, and form a naturally and 
closely connected series, — Arithmetic, Plane Geo- 
metry, Solid Geometry, Astronomy, and Harmonics. 
Even the two latter deal not with physical things, — 
the visible luminaries of the sky, and the musical 
sounds of the voice and other instruments, — but 
with permanent truths, mathematical relations, which 
eye cannot see nor ear hear. 

Plato gives, in the seventh book of the Republic, 
a very remarkable account of the sciences conversant 
with conceptions. To that account it must suffice 
here merely to refer. The great value of those 
sciences in his view was that they tended to raise 



CLASSIFICATION OF THE SCIENCES. 73 

the mind above themselves, to develop philosophic 
insight, to educate reason to apprehend the absolute 
truth which is the light and life of the soul. In 
themselves he regarded them as inherently defective. 
They begin with certain assumptions and give us 
only the consequences which follow from reasoning 
on these assumptions. They start from principles 
which they cannot prove, which it is beyond their 
province to prove. They are essentially hypothetical. 
There is need, accordingly, for a higher science; 
a science which may make use of the assumptions of 
the sciences which deal with conceptions as occasions 
and starting-points whence it may ascend to absolute 
principles, to what has its reality and evidence in 
itself, to ideas. And there is such a science. Its 
name is Dialectic. The lower sciences have for their 
objects conceptions or scientific assumptions; the 
faculty which they employ is discursive reason, and 
their procedure is demonstration. The highest 
science has for its objects ideas, not conceptions; 
absolute, not hypothetical principles; real, not 
assumed existences; for its process intuition, not 
demonstration, and for its faculty the intuitive, not 
the discursive reason. It includes in itself all pro- 
perly philosophical investigations. It is at once a 
metaphysics, a logic, a theology, an ethics, and an 
aesthetics ; a metaphysics, because occupied with the 
immutable and invisible ; a logic, because the form 



74 PLATONIC SCHEME OF 

and method of absolute science ; a theology, because 
the supreme idea is the ultimate cause ; an ethics, 
inasmuch as conversant with the principles which 
are the source of all morality; and an aesthetics, 
since true beauty is ideal and transcendental in 
nature and origin. 

Plato's doctrine of science originated in a profound 
conception of the nature of intelligence, and corre- 
sponded to a magnificent view of the universe of 
existence. From its promulgation to the present 
time it has captivated alike the reason, imaginations, 
and moral susceptibilities of men as no similar theory 
has done. But, whatever were its merits, it had also 
defects, which showed themselves very plainly in the 
Platonic survey of the sciences, and which led, in 
particular, to undue contraction of the sphere of 
science. The whole world of sense is not to be 
relegated, as Plato advised, to the limbo of mere 
opinion. Natural apprehension and ordinary judg- 
ment are not so essentially different from scientific 
cognition as he assumed. The notion that there is 
no science of phenomena, and that consequently 
science cannot be reached through the study of 
phenomena, but requires us to get beyond phen- 
omena, through and above them as it were, into 
a region of types, exemplars, conceptions, ideas, is 
directly antagonistic to the spirit of modern science, 
and has been amply confuted by the splendid achieve- 



CLASSIFICATION OF THE SCIENCES. 75 

ments of modern science. It is a notion which 
involves denial of the possibility of the physical or 
natural sciences. 

It apparently led Plato to that conclusion. For 
although in the Timaeus he speculated on the origin 
and disposition of the world, and the organisation of 
man, he expressly held that nothing could be affirmed 
on these subjects as certain. What is called his 
Physics was an application of his Dialectics, and of 
a character which he himself maintained must be 
conjectural. Of physical science in the proper sense 
he has shown, I think, no conception. The error 
which led him thus unduly to restrict the sphere of 
science he also carried into his actual survey and 
description of the sciences. There it took the form 
of the dogma that the realities of a science are dis- 
tinct from its phenomena. The latter do not contain 
or manifest, but only suggest the truths of science, 
and aid the mind to reach them. The conceptions 
of Geometry are ideal assumptions ; its phenomena 
are visible illustrations which never exactly cor- 
respond to them, and often do them great injustice. 
So there is an Astronomy of theories or realities, and 
an Astronomy of appearances or phenomena ; and 
the latter is not true Astronomy, because the varie- 
gated adornments which appear in the sky, the visible 
luminaries, beautiful as they are, are only a sort of 
admirable diagrams by the help of which we may 



76 PLATONIC SCHEME OF 

rise to the contemplation of spheres, movements, 
and relations, which are real and immutable, and 
which can be grasped only in mental conception. 

Now, all that is untenable. The diagrams of the 
geometer are not phenomena of geometry. Geo- 
metrical reasoning refers entirely to ideal figures 
and relations, understanding thereby immediately 
or mediately defined figures in immediately or 
mediately defined relations. However badly drawn 
may be the diagrams before the bodily eye of the 
geometer, those before his mental eye are always 
absolutely accurate delineations. He can only 
reason on the supposition that his triangles, squares, 
&c, are precisely what they are defined to be. 
It is likewise vain to separate and contrast an 
astronomy of appearances and an astronomy of 
theories. The appearances are in astronomy the 
very things and the only things to be explained. 
A theory, to be of any worth, must be one which 
accounts for the appearances. Plato failed to per- 
ceive how phenomena exhibit laws and how laws 
manifest themselves in phenomena, and conse- 
quently he opposed phenomena to realities in a 
way which few will now undertake to defend. 

Apart from the error indicated, Plato's survey of 
the hypothetical sciences — the sciences which deal 
with conceptions — is of remarkable merit, consider- 
ing the age to which it belongs. It is especially 



CLASSIFICATION OF THE SCIENCES. 77 

meritorious for the comprehensiveness and correct- 
ness of mathematical view which it displays. It 
strongly corroborates the historical testimony that 
Plato was a proficient in the mathematical knowledge 
of his time. He ignored, as we have seen, natural 
science. Here, where Aristotle was so powerful, 
Plato was comparatively feeble; but, on the other 
hand, where Aristotle was weakest Plato was 
strongest. All the difficulties which intelligence 
meets with may be reduced to two classes,— diffi- 
culties of abstraction and difficulties of complexity. 
Of superior minds some overcome more easily 
the one class of difficulties and some the other class. 
Aristotle was the more fitted to deal with the 
complex, Plato with the abstract. Hence, Aristotle 
was drawn to natural philosophy, and still more to 
natural history and psychology, and whatever de- 
manded close observation and searching analysis; 
Plato to mathematics, and all those loftier problems 
which most transcend sense and most exercise pure 
intellect. Few thinkers have discerned so broadly 
and clearly as Plato the relations of the mathe- 
matical sciences to philosophy. 

Aristotle's conception of philosophy as distin- Arkto- 
guished from science was greatly inferior to that gcheme. 
of Plato, and his criticism of the nature of know- 
ledge was far less profound and suggestive, yet his 



78 ARISTOTELIAN DISTRIBUTION 

work was, on the whole, an advance on that of his 
predecessor. It was at once its continuation and 
complement. Aristotle collected the truths which 
Plato had so lavishly scattered, added to them a 
multitude of facts acquired by his own indefatigable 
industry, and a multitude of reflections suggested 
by his own vigorous and penetrating intellect, and 
combined with rare judgment his vast acquisitions 
into distinct organic systems. He thus became the 
founder of more sciences than any other man. He 
gave existence and form to almost as many special 
scientific disciplines as he wrote books. 

That great thinker, than whom there probably 
never lived a man of more encyclopaedic mind, 
adopted a threefold division of philosophy, science, 
or knowledge. He distributed it into Theoretic, 
Productive, and Practical Theoretic Philosophy 
has no aim beyond the apprehension of truth. It 
is conversant with the existent, with being. It 
subdivides into Physics, Mathematics, and Meta- 
physics. Being, considered in connection with 
whatever can be known through perception and 
experience, is the subject-matter of Physics, which, 
according to Aristotle, includes Psychology. Being, 
conceived of apart from the variations of the mate- 
rial world, but not apart from matter, is that with 
which Mathematics is conversant. Mathematics 
consequently differs from Physics not essentially, 



OP KNOWLEDGE. 79 

but only in degree, as being more general and 
abstract. Metaphysics, again, differs from Mathe- 
matics just as Mathematics differs from Physics, 
being still more general and abstract. It treats of 
Being per se, of the existent in its absolute nature 
and universal properties. Aristotle called it " First 
Philosophy," and sometimes " Theology. " It con- 
tained what little theology he taught. 

But philosophy, according to Aristotle, although 
primarily is not exclusively theoretic. The con- 
templation of being is its proper function in its 
purest form, but not its only function. It has 
regard also to the production of effects and to the 
regulation of human actions. In the former case 
it is Productive Philosophy ; in the latter case it is 
Practical Philosophy. Productive Philosophy differs 
from Theoretic Philosophy because it tends to per- 
formance instead of to contemplation, and 'from 
Practical Philosophy because it does not terminate 
in the regulation of actions, but in the origination of 
permanent products. It is the theory of the arts. 
Aristotle did not subdivide it. His " Poetics " deals 
only with one of the "imitative" arts. Rhetoric, 
which, judging from its general character, one ex- 
pects to find placed by the side of Poetics, was 
viewed by him as a science auxiliary to Politics. 
Practical Philosophy looks beyond truth to the 
good, and seeks so to regulate actions that the good 



80 ARISTOTELIAN DISTRIBUTION OP KNOWLEDGE. 

may be reached. Its two chief branches are Ethics 
and Politics. The former deals with man in relation 
to his natural good as an individual ; the latter is 
an inquiry as to how society should be constituted 
.with a view to the public good. 

Within this scheme Aristotle did not place Ana- 
lytics, later called Logic. He regarded it not as a 
part of philosophy, but as an introduction to philo- 
sophy, and especially to "first philosophy." As a 
doctrine of the principles and processes of science 
he considered that it ought to take precedence of 
the sciences. This, of course, was virtually to 
exclude it from the sciences and to allow that the 
proposed classification of the sciences was not in- 
clusive of all departments of knowledge, while it 
could, with much appearance at least of truth, be 
maintained that the principles and processes of 
science are only ascertainable after sciences have 
been formed. Logic may, however, have a place 
assigned it within the Aristotelian scheme. It may, 
indeed, be ranked either among the Productive or 
the Practical Sciences ; among the former if its end 
be supposed to be the production of arguments; 
among the latter if it be held to aim at the regu- 
lation of the reasoning faculty. Rhetoric, also, is 
virtually excluded from the classification when re- 
presented as simply an auxiliary to Politics. It too, 
however, like Logic, may easily be placed within it, 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 81 

and either as a Productive or a Practical Science, — 
the former if its aim be deemed the production of 
orations, the latter if it be regarded as looking to 
influence on the mind and conduct. Economics is 
conjoined by Aristotle with Rhetoric, as being also 
a science auxiliary to Politics. It might just as well 
be viewed as a constituent member of the group of 
Practical Sciences. 

The work which Aristotle accomplished in the 
way of originating and advancing the sciences which 
he arranged or classified according to the plan now 
described, gained him a unique position in the 
history of science. No one has attained, or can 
reasonably hope to attain, any very like position. 
The scheme of classification itself, however, has 
obvious defects. Thus, in the first place, the dis- 
tinction between Productive Sciences and Practical 
Sciences ought not to have the importance which is 
assigned to it. It is neither broad nor deep, and 
certainly not fundamental or primary. Nay, it is 
much to be doubted whether it is a distinction 
which can be at all applied to separate and distri- 
bute the sciences. For as every science is in some 
measure both regulative of actions and productive 
of results, it would seem that there must be arbi- 
trariness in forming sciences into groups by view- 
ing some sciences as only regulative of actions and 
others as only productive of results. Aristotle 

F 



82 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

chose to regard Politics, for example, as a Practical 
Science, but he might with equal reason have ranked 
it as a Productive Science. He might have looked 
at the result it seeks to accomplish rather than at 
its character as a means, and the result is a perma- 
nent product, — an orderly, prosperous, and endur- 
ing society. 

In the second place, it is erroneous to classify the 
sciences according to ends, either of regulation or 
production. They should be arranged according to 
their natures, their inherent characteristics, not 
according to anything lying beyond themselves. 
The end of a science is not anything fixed. It is 
the sum of the uses to which the science can be put, 
and uses always vary with wants. One science may 
have many ends, and many sciences may require to 
be combined in order to gain one end. It must 
be especially erroneous to arrange some sciences 
according to their natures and others according 
to their ends. It must be illegitimate to employ 
two principles of classification, and when one 
fails, to have recourse to the other. That is a 
procedure which must at once give rise to cross- 
divisions, and which has in itself no logical limits. 
If we can introduce two principles, why not three ? 
And if three, why not as many as there are 
things to divide? There can be no legitimate 
scheme of classification in which the divisions 



CLARIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 83 

are not determined throughout by one common 
principle. 

That leads me to say that a third, and perhaps 
the greatest, defect of the Aristotelian survey of the 
sciences was the want of unity which arose from the 
absence of a philosophy inclusive of, but superior to, 
the sciences. Without explicitly affirming that he 
did so, he, in reality, viewed philosophy as merely 
a whole constituted by the sciences, a sum made up 
of the sciences as a unit is made up of its component 
fractions. But this leaves no philosophy distinct 
from the sciences, and either able or entitled to co- 
ordinate and organise them. Hence in the Aristo- 
telian arrangement there is a certain grouping of 
the sciences, but not a real systemisation of them. 
They are not shown to constitute an organic whole. 
They have each an independent foundation, and 
they are also in some degree classified, but there is 
no highest science to comprehend them and to de- 
termine the place of each. What Aristotle called 
First Philosophy and his commentators Metaphysics, 
does not perform this function. Its object is being 
as being, and so it is the antecedent and presup- 
position of all other sciences, since they all treat of 
special concrete beings, but it possesses a merely 
abstract universality, and it has no power nor is it 
any part of its business to organise the various 
sciences into a system. It is not, to use an Aristo- 



84 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

telian word, an architectonic science. The science 
which Aristotle himself regards as such is Politics, 
but its claims to the honour are altogether inadmis- 
sible. They amount merely to an affirmation that 
Politics is entitled to control other sciences, seeing 
that politicians must view the sciences in relation to 
the public good. We may be sure, however, that 
the order of the sciences has a far deeper source 
than the will and the interest of men. It must 
spring from the essential truth of things, from the 
all-pervasive order of nature. 
Modified The Aristotelian classification, notwithstanding its 
ian dasBi" radical defects, was widely accepted, although only 
fication. ^ a giightly modified form. The narrow, the 
really untenable distinction between Productive 
and Practical Sciences was dropped, and philosophy 
came to be divided simply into two great branches, 
the Theoretical and Practical. This division found 
recognition both among the Stoics and the Epi- 
cureans. Some expressed it by representing Philo- 
sophy as either Physical or Ethical, i.e., either 
concerned with the contemplation of nature or the 
regulation of human action. The great objection 
to it is that it identified, or rather confounded, 
philosophy with science. It recognised no philo- 
sophy distinct from the sciences. It assumed that 
the branches of philosophy were the divisions of 
the sciences. If that be the case there is either 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 85 

no philosophy proper or no science proper, for either 
philosophy absorbs the sciences or the sciences leave 
no room for philosophy. The division of the 
sciences into Theoretical and Practical is still a 
favourite popular one. There can be little doubt, 
however, that it is faulty, even when science and 
philosophy are expressly distinguished. All the 
so-called Theoretical Sciences may be regarded as 
also Practical Sciences, and all the Practical Sciences 
as also Theoretical Sciences, if each class be only 
looked at from the point of view previously appro- 
priated to the other. 

The division of philosophy into Dialectics, Physics, 
and Ethics, commonly but erroneously attributed to 
Plato, has been also referred to Aristotle, although 
it is, of course, admitted not to have been the one 
which he himself adopted. It has been referred to, 
however, on the authority of a passage which by 
no means warrants the conclusion drawn from it. 
In that passage (Topics, B. I. ch. xiv.) he says that 
" there are three parts of propositions and of pro- 
blems; for some propositions are ethical, others 
physical, and others logical " ; and he says so only 
when treating of the choice of propositions with 
reference to disputation. To regard that as a 
division of philosophy into Physics, Ethics, and 
Logic is to raise a very large superstructure on a 
very small foundation. To classify propositions 



86 



CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 



with reference to a particular end is a very differ- 
ent thing from classifying the sciences. Besides, 
Aristotle put forth his classification of propositions 
as only generally, only in outline, true (£9 rvma 
wepikafUzlv). 



Stoic Mid 
Epicurean 

diatribu- 
tion of 
Bcienoee. 



The threefold division of philosophy into Logic, 
Physics, and Ethics can be fairly ascribed neither 
to Plato or Aristotle. It may have been enunci- 
ated by Xenocrates, as Sextus Empiricus says, but 
there is now no proof of that, and not unlikely it 
originated with those who attached so much im- 
portance to it, the Stoics, They regarded all 
knowledge as vain and superfluous which had no 
end beyond itself,— which did not help towards 
the attainment of that wisdom to which the charac- 
ter and conduct ought to conform. They held 
that philosophy existed only to perfect human 
nature and to guide human life, and that in order 
to secure this end it must elicit and cultivate three 
virtues or excellences : it must train the under- 
standing to distinguish the true from the falsi.' , 
the useful from the useless, must enable the intel- 
lect to penetrate into the nature and trace the 
order of the universe, and must regulate the will 
in the practice of what is good ; in other words, it 
must be a Logic, Physics, and Ethics, — a Logic to 
guide the reason, a Physics to explain the world, 






CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE 3CIENCES. 87 

and an Ethics to rule the moral life. Each of those 
disciplines was deemed to include two sciences. 
Logic was not only the science of correct thinking, 
but of the correct expression of thought, and so 
comprehended both Dialectic and Rhetoric ; Physics 
was both a Cosmology and a Theology, Deity being 
regarded as not separable from the world, but the 
active and formative power immanent in it; and 
Ethics embraced Morals and Politics. The Stoics 
were not agreed as to the order in which Logic, 
Physics, and Ethics ought to stand. They com- 
monly placed Logic first, but were much divided 
as to whether Physics should precede or follow 
Ethics. Logic they likened to the bones and 
sinews of the animal body and to the shell of an 
egg, but while some thought Physics was like the 
flesh of the beast and white of the egg, and Ethics 
like the soul of the one and the yolk of the other, 
others represented Ethics as the flesh and white, 
and Physics as the soul and yolk The Epicureans 
accepted the same threefold division of science, but 
without differing among themselves as to the order 
of the divisions. They were still more narrowly 
and exclusively practical than the Stoics; they 
looked on philosophy merely as the power which 
conducts men to happiness, and as worth attention 
only in so far as it contributes to render existence 
agreeable ; hence, Logic they confined to an investi- 



88 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

gation of the criteria of truth, and cultivated simply 
as necessary to Physics, and Physics they entirely 
subordinated to Ethics, valuing it only as the means 
of delivering the mind from superstitious beliefs 
which disquiet and embitter the life. 

It is unnecessary to criticise this distribution of 
science either in its Stoic or Epicurean form. It is 
very obvious that it finds no proper place for, if it 
does not expressly exclude, metaphysics, mathematics, 
psychology, and theology ; and, in fact, that it ex- 
cludes at least as much as it includes. It received, 
however, a wide acceptance, rivalling, and perhaps 
even exceeding, in its diffusion the Aristotelian 
classification. It prevailed among the scholastics, 
and has found favour even with Descartes, Locke, 
Kant, Herbert, and Hegel, although they have, of 
course, suggested certain real or supposed improve- 
ments. It will, therefore, come before us again in 
later and more elaborated forms. 

Vwto. Cicero has no claim to a place in this history, but 

his contemporary and friend, the learned and inde- 
fatigable Varro, is entitled to be mentioned as, in 
all probability, the first who composed a kind of 
inventory or encyclopaedia of the sciences. Like 
all but two of the 490 works which he wrote, his 
treatise Libri novem disciplinarum has been lost 
for ages, but it exerted an influence, through the 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 89 

writings of Capella, Cassiodorus, and others, on 
many generations to which it was unknown. The 
nine disciplines of which he treated were the seven 
so-called " liberal arts," with the addition of medi- 
cine and architecture. 

In the fifth century of the Christian era, Marti- Capeik. 
anus Capella wrote his bizarre encyclopaedic ro- 
mance, the Satyricon. Two books describe the 
marriage of Mercury and Philology, the daughter 
of Phronesis, and the remaining seven are devoted 
to the seven attendants on the bride, the seven 
liberal arts, — Grammar, Dialectic, Rhetoric, Geo- 
metry, Arithmetic, Astronomy, Music. 

Somewhat later Cassiodorus treated of the same Cumo- 
departments of knowledge in his De artibus et dis- 
ciplinis liberalium litterarum, grouping together 
Grammar, Dialectic, and Rhetoric, as Artes or 
ScienticB Sermocinales, and Arithmetic, Geometry, 
Astronomy, and Music as Disciplines or Sdentiw 
Reales. Capella and Cassiodorus definitively estab- 
lished the educational curriculum for the studious 
youth of medieval Europe. It has to be remem- 
bered, however, that it was only a preparatory 
course. The studies which it comprised were all 
regarded as ancillary to a higher science, as so many 
steps and supports leading up to the knowledge of 
divine things, the mistress science, Theology. 

They were grouped into what was called the 



90 



CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 



Trivium 
and Quad- 



Trivium and Quadriviuni ; the fornier comprehend- 
ing Grammar, Dialectic, and Rhetoric, and the 
latter Arithmetic, Geometry, Astronomy, and Music, 
The general thought which underlay this division of 
studies was that those of the lower order were con- 
versant with words, those of the higher with things; 
that the former were, as they were often termed, 
dm serniocinaleSi the litter scientits reales; or, 
otherwise, that the former were Logica, the latter 
Mathematica. The Trivium corresponded likewise 
to the Logic, and the Quadrivium to the Physics of 
the Stoics. Ethics was generally included by the 
Scholastics in Theology, although it was sometimes 
given a place apart. It was usual for students to 
pass slowly through the Trivium and rapidly 
through the Quadrivium, and not uncommon for 
them to omit the latter altogether, so as to pass 
at once from logical and verbal studies to what was 
then the science of most engrossing interest. This, 
more than any other fact, perhaps, is explanatory 
of Scholasticism. The scholastics were men whose 
minds were nurtured on words divorced from things 
and on the forms without the realities of know- 
ledge. Even the medieval so-called "real sciences" 
were essentially formal sciences; Arithmetic and 
Geometry manifestly so, and Astronomy and Music 
less plainly yet, in the main, indubitably so, as the 
physical bases and material contents of both these 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 91 

sciences were almost wholly ignored. No wonder, 
therefore, that so many of the representatives of 
scholasticism should now seem to us, as we look 
back upon their exertions, like " metaphysic mills 
vigorous in grinding the air." 

Isidore of Seville (560-636), a celebrated Spanish Isidore, 
bishop, and two illustrious Englishmen, the Vener- 
able Bede (673-735) and Alcuin (736-804), greatly 
contributed to give currency and authority to the 
scheme of classification of the sciences introduced 
by Capella and Cassiodorus. Isidore did so by the 
work entitled Originum s. Etymologiarum Libri xx, 
which at the time of its appearance, and for several 
centuries afterwards, was supposed to form a com- 
plete encyclopaedia of all extant departments of 
knowledge. It was the chief source from which in 
those times general information was drawn, and had 
there been no such book, the darkest period of the 
medieval world would have been even darker than 
it was. The author's scheme and description of the 
sciences are contained in his first three books, and 
the order of their arrangement runs thus : (1) Gram- 
mar, (2) Khetoric, (3) Dialectic, (4) Arithmetic, (5) 
Geometry, (6) Music, (7) Astronomy, (8) Medicine, 
(9) Jurisprudence, and (10) Chronology. 

The influence of Bede, owing to his zeal for Bede and 
acquiring and diffusing knowledge, his piety, his cum * 
authorship of such a work as the Historia Ecclesi- 



92 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

astica Gentis Britonum, and the compends which 
he wrote to facilitate for students a mastery over 
various disciplince, could not fail to be strong and 
of the same character and tendency as Isidore's. 
Alcuin, doubtless, owed much to what Bede had 
been and done, but he was called to work in a far 
wider sphere. Fortunately, he was well prepared 
for his mission in life by an admirable and appro- 
priate education in the renowned schools of York, 
and when he became the friend and preceptor of 
Charlemagne he zealously sought to have similar 
schools founded throughout that monarch's wide 
empire. The king was his first pupil, gave him 
always his complete confidence, and placed him 
wherever he could be of most use. During the last 
years of Alcuin's life he was abbot of the famous 
monastery of St Martin of Tours, and there, as he 
had done in other positions, he gave not only 
lessons on the Bible, but also on ancient languages, 
grammar, rhetoric, dialectic, and astronomy. 

Between the ninth and twelfth century there was 
little if anything which here concerns us. It must 
be remembered, however, that from the twelfth 
century onwards the scholastic doctors, although 
not independent students of the sciences, or com- 
petent to organise satisfactorily the system of the 
sciences, knew all that Aristotle had taught, much 
besides which the Jews and Arabs had added, and 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 93 

the vast body of doctrines which had been gradu- 
ally derived from the statements or suggestions of 
Scripture. Only minds of the largest capacity 
could contain those stores of thought and learning 
possessed by an Albertus Magnus, a Thomas 
Aquinas, or a Dante. 

The most characteristic medieval attempts at 
classification of the various kinds of knowledge 
were those which subordinated all secular studies 
to theology, and represented the former as so many 
stages by which the soul might gradually raise itself 
to communion with the Divine. It may suffice to 
indicate the character of three such attempts, viz., 
those of Hugo of St Victor, St Bonaventura, and 
Vincent of Beauvais. Mysticism was a prominent 
feature of all three, and the mysticism was of a 
kind which has been appropriately called Latin, in 
order to distinguish it from the earlier Greek mysti- 
cism of the pseudo-Dionysius and Scotus Erigena 
and the later German mysticism of Eckhart, Tauler, 
and Thomas k Kempis. In all three stages medi- 
eval mysticism was prominent, and naturally so as 
a much-needed counterpoise to the crude and coarse 
views, the empiricism, dogmatism, and formalism so 
prevalent in the medieval world. 



The classification of Hugo of St Victor (1096- Hugo of 
1141) is to be found in his Eruditio didiscalica. 



94 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

Three books in that work treat of worldly sciences, 
and four of sacred and ecclesiastical history. The 
former are of most interest. The main object of the 
entire work, however, is distinctly avowed to be to 
serve as a propedeutic to theology. All kinds of 
secular knowledge are held to be of right subor- 
dinate and auxiliary to religion. The entire scheme 
of classification is comprised in three classes or divi- 
sions. First, there are the theoretical sciences. 
These include, — physics (which is occupied with 
what is temporal and material), — mathematics 
(which is represented as comprehending the whole 
four divisions of the quadrivium, not merely arith- 
metic and geometry but also astronomy and music), 
— and above all theology (the object of which is the 
eternal and divine, and in which alone the reason 
and heart can find their full satisfaction). Secondly, 
there is the division of practical sciences. It is held 
to consist of ethics, economics, and politics. And, 
thirdly, there is a sevenfold distribution of so-called 
mechanical or technical arts. They are arranged in 
the following order, — weaving, smith-work, naviga- 
tion, agriculture, hunting, medicine, and the histri- 
onic art. When one considers that Hugo was a 
thorough recluse, of a feeble and sickly constitu- 
tion, and who is said to have been only once away 
from his monastery, it must seem marvellous that he 
should have been able to acquire so much know- 
ledge as he did of such arts as those mentioned. 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 95 

He did not include psychology in his classification, 
but he was a student of psychical facts. As he 
assigned the different faculties of mind to different 
divisions of the brain, he may be held to have so 
far anticipated the phrenology of Gall and Spurz- 
heim. In that, however, he was not original. 
Phrenology should be regarded as not a modern 
but a medieval invention. 

The " Seraphic Doctor," St Bonaventura (1221- Bonaven- 
1274), wrote a treatise entitled De reductione ar- 
tium ad theologiam, in which he sought to refer the 
varieties of knowledge to the one source of truth — 
the Father of light. Cognitions he distributed 
into artificial, natural, intellectual, and revealed, 
according to the character of the Divine illumina- 
tion in which he supposed them to originate ; for, 
in this view, there are four kinds or degrees of 
light, — the external light, by which we learn the 
mechanical arts, — the inferior light, which shines 
through the senses, and by which we apprehend 
individuals or things, — the internal light, the 
reason, which by reflection raises the soul to in- 
tellectual things, the universals in conception, — 
and the superior light, the light of grace, which 
reveals to us sanctifying virtue, and elevates us to 
universals as they are in their reality — i.e., in God 
himself. It is, according to Bonaventura, from the 
internal light that theoretic science or philosophy 



96 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

flows, and such science or philosophy may be three- 
fold, natural, rational, and moral, — the natural in- 
cluding the three sciences of physics, mathematics, 
and metaphysics, — the rational those of grammar, 
logic, and rhetoric, — and the moral those of ethics, 
economics, and politics. 

Vincent of A contemporary of Bonaventura, Vincent of Beau- 
r. Bacon, v &is, w &s the author of a very learned work of an 
and Dante, encyclopaedic nature, the Bibliotheca mundi, other- 
wise known as the Speculum quadruplex, since the 
first part was meant to be a "mirror of nature" 
(speculum naturale) ; the second a " mirror of doc- 
trine " or science (speculum doctrinale) ; the third a 
" mirror of history " (speculum historiale) ; and the 
fourth a " mirror of morals " (speculum morale). In 
the same century Roger Bacon did noble service to 
the cause of science by insisting on the regard due 
to experience, and enlarged men's conceptions of its 
domain by his advocacy of linguistic, optical, and 
experimental studies. 

Some of our readers will recall to mind how 
Dante in his Convito has represented the dis- 
tribution of the sciences as corresponding to the 
divisions of the heavens. Heaven in general 
is science in general, — science abstract and un- 
divided, — and as there are ten heavens, so are 
there ten spheres of science. The seven heavens 



CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 97 

nearest to the earth are those of the planets, and 
the planets in ascending order are as follows, — the 
Moon, Mercury, Venus, the Sun, Mars, Jupiter, and 
Saturn; to them correspond the seven sciences of 
the Trivium and Quadrivium ; and mysterious ana- 
logies — so the poet, with an imaginative subtility 
impossible to describe, seeks to prove — exist be- 
tween each planet and the science of which it is a 
symbol, — between the Moon and grammar, Mercury 
and dialectics, Venus and rhetoric, the Sun and 
arithmetic, Mars and music, Jupiter and geometry, 
Saturn and astronomy. Above those planetary 
heavens are three others, the heaven of the fixed 
stars, the crystalline heaven, and the heaven of 
eternal rest, the all-embracing empyrean, not in 
space but formed solely in the primal Mind ; and 
these heavens represent the highest sciences, — the 
starry sphere corresponding to physics and meta- 
physics united, the crystalline to moral philosophy, 
and the empyrean to theology. 



n. FROM THE RENAISSANCE TO KANT. 

We must come down to the Renaissance period PoiiaMio. 
before we meet with any better schemes of scientific 
co-ordination. The Panepistemon (published in 
1491) of the renowned poet and classicist, Angelo 



98 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

Poliziano, was merely a prelude to more serious 
attempts. It delineates the tree of knowledge as 
dividing into the three great branches of revela- 
tion, of discovery, and of divination. To revelation 
corresponds positive theology, — the theology which 
springs from the fountain of inspiration. To dis- 
covery or invention corresponds philosophy, of which 
the general divisions are these three, — 1. Specta- 
tiva 9 theoretic or intuitive, including mathematics, 
physics, psychology, and ontology with natural 
theology; 2. Actualis, practical, comprising ethics, 
economics, and politics ; and 3. Bationalis, rational, 
conversant with grammar the art of expression, 
history the art of narration, dialectics the art of 
demonstration, rhetoric the art of persuasion, and 
poetics the art of intellectual delectation. 
Nisoiio. There is some originality in the scheme of classi- 
fication propounded by Mario Nizolio in his De 
veris principiis et vera ratione philosophandi 
contra pseudophilosophos (1553). Nizolio was a 
keen opponent of scholasticism, an extreme nomin- 
alist, and a decided positivist almost three hundred 
years before Comte. He held that metaphysics was 
either false or useless, and to be excluded from 
among the sciences (partim falsam, partim inu- 
tilem et supervecuam . . . ab omni artium et 
scientiarum numero removendam). He equally re- 
jected dialectics and sought to retain only a logic 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 99 

which would concern itself simply with experience, 
induction, and the simple, clear, and correct use of 
words. He laid great stress on language, holding 
thought and speech to be related as soul and body. 
Hence he represented the tree of the sciences and 
arts as primarily dividing into the two branches of 
Philosophy and Oratory, the former tending to 
wisdom and the latter to its appropriate expression. 
Philosophy he distributed into natural (Physics) 
and civil (Politics), — natural philosophy including 
geography, meteorology, physiology, and even the- 
ology, — and moral philosophy comprising ethics, 
politics in the special sense of the word, economics, 
jurisprudence, &c. Under Oratoria he ranked all 
disciplines conversant with speech and composition, 
e.g., grammar, rhetoric, poetics, and history. At 
the same time he admitted that numerous depart- 
ments of knowledge and practice, such as the var- 
ious branches of mathematics, the mechanical arts, 
the fine arts, and medicine, could not be included 
simply and entirely under any one of these three 
great divisions — Physics, Politics, Oratory — but 
must be referred to two or even to all of them. 

Now we reach Thomas Campanella (1568-1639), campan- 
who was one of the best representatives in Italy of e 
that great movement of philosophical reform which 
in the same age produced DesCartes in France and 



100 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

Bacon in England. Like these two great men he 
refused to be the slave of the past or to bow down 
to authority, — summoned the real and reputed 
doctrines of Aristotle before the bar of reason in 
order to be tried and tested by their conformity to, 
or deviation from, nature, — and sought, by substi- 
tuting experience and induction for dogmatism and 
a priori reasoning, to reconstruct the whole edifice 
of science, — while, by the courage with which he 
braved danger and the patience with which he 
endured persecution, he displayed a strength of soul 
of which both were destitute and which entitles 
him to a place in the foremost rank alike of the 
heroes and martyrs of all time. Campanella, as 
well as his great English contemporary, endeavoured 
not only to recall men from an old and false to a 
new and true method of scientific inquiry, but to 
map out the provinces of knowledge according to 
their natural order and relationship. It must be 
admitted, however, that in this part of his task his 
services were less brilliant than those of Bacon; 
that he has not lavished on it the same intellectual 
wealth; or indicated with the same clearness of 
vision on his chart of the intellectual world where 
there are lands to discover; or given utterance to 
the same magnificent prophecies respecting the 
future of science. But if his conceptions were not 
so large and magnificent, neither were they so 



CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 101 

vague and confused The principle of his classi- 
fication was also sounder, inasmuch as he did not 
set out from a purely subjective position, but 
aimed at an objective arrangement : in other words, 
he attempted to classify knowledge not according 
to the faculties conversant with it, but according 
to its own nature. 

According to Campanella, all knowledge is latent 
and in germ in sensation, — sentire est scire, — but 
it can only be realised and rendered explicit by 
intellection ascending from the immediate to the 
remote, from the known to the unknown, from per- 
ception to theory. The foundation, consequently, 
of all science is history, and as history is either 
divine or human, the sciences must be divided 
into divine and human. God is the truth, and all 
truth must be received from him, but he gives truth 
in two ways, — he places the book of nature before 
our eyes, and he speaks to us through the prophets 
and in our own hearts. Revelation and nature, 
these are the two sources of all knowledge, the 
primary divine autographs of which all human 
systems are but the imperfect and inaccurate copies, 
and with which they need to be constantly com- 
pared to see if they contain anything false. On 
revelation theology must be built; on nature, 
micrology. Micrology in its turn is divided in a 
twofold way, into natural and moral science; the 



102 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

principal branches of the former being geometry, 
cosmography, astronomy, astrology, and medicine; 
and of the latter, ethics, politics, and economics, 
with rhetoric and poetic as auxiliaries. All these 
sciences, however, treat of particular objects, and 
there must be another which treats of the universal. 
They are but parts of a whole ; and there must be a 
study which shows how they are so concentrated 
and co-ordinated as to form the whole, and what 
principles pervade and unify them. This study is 
metaphysics. Its office is to supply principles to 
all the arts and sciences, and it comprehends a 
threefold inquiry, namely: (1) into principles of 
knowledge, (2) into principles of existence, and (3) 
into principles of action. 

Thus Campanella surveyed the domain of science 
and mapped out its provinces. It is unnecessary 
to criticise its details, its subordinate divisions, and 
its delineations of the limits of the special sciences. 
These, of course, were not, and could not be expected 
to be, correct. It is of more importance to note that 
there is hardly a part of the scheme — scarcely a 
science included in it — on which Campanella has 
not written with learning and ingenuity; that in 
holding that a classification of the sciences ought to 
have regard to their objective aspects, their own 
natures, their inherent characteristics, he took up 
the only right position; and that in representing 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 103 

theology as overlying and metaphysics as under- 
lying all the other sciences, and the intervening 
sciences as composed of two series of sciences, he 
made a remarkable approximation to a system 
of co-ordination of the sciences true at least in 
outline. 

DesCartes has not entered on the subject under DeeCarte* 
consideration in any formal or elaborate manner. 
The most explicit passage regarding it in his writings 
is the following : " When a man has acquired some 
skill in discovering truth, he should commence to 
apply himself in earnest to true philosophy, of which 
the first part is Metaphysics, containing the prin- 
ciples of knowledge, among which is the explication 
of the principal attributes of God, of the immortal- 
ity of the soul, and of all the clear and simple 
notions that are in us; the second is Physics, in 
which, after finding the true principles of material 
things, we examine, in general, how the whole uni- 
verse has been framed; in the next place, we 
consider, in particular, the nature of the earth, and 
of all the bodies that are most generally found 
upon it, as air, water, fire, the loadstone, and other 
minerals ; in the next place, it is necessary also to 
examine singly the nature of plants, of animals, and 
above all of man, in order that we may thereafter 
be able to discover the other sciences that are useful 



104 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

to us. Thus, all Philosophy is like a tree, of which 
Metaphysics is the root, Physics the trunk, and all 
the other sciences the branches that grow out of this 
trunk, which are reduced to three principal, namely, 
Medicine, Mechanics, and Ethics. By the science 
of Morals I understand the highest and most perfect 
which, presupposing an entire knowledge of the 
other sciences, is the last degree of wisdom." x 

In the context DesCartes informs us that he 
meant by Philosophy "all that the human mind 
can know," so that his distribution of Philosophy 
must be regarded as a distribution of all knowledge. 
Logic, indeed, he did not include, although he had 
been speaking of it immediately before, because he 
looked on logic from an altogether practical point 
of view, so that it was in his eyes not a part, but the 
method, of philosophy. Notwithstanding this, his 
division was nearly the same as that generally 
adopted by his followers — e.g., by Sylvain Regis, 
Clauberg, Geulinx — viz., a fourfold division into 
Logic, Metaphysics, Physics, and Ethics. 

Baconian The Baconian survey of the sciences is a very 
celebrated one. I venture not to pronounce it 
unworthy of its fame, although I cannot regard 
even its leading divisions as accurate. If not a 
particularly accurate, it was a comprehensive and 

1 Preface to the Principles of Philosophy. 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 105 

attractive, sketch of the intellectual world, in- 
dicating in a striking way, difficult to forget, 
not only what provinces had been acquired by 
the human mind, but where, and in what manner, 
new conquests were still to be made. It is difficult 
to judge what importance Bacon himself attached 
to it; probably he valued it chiefly because it 
afforded a convenient framework within which he 
could arrange his criticisms and counsels regarding 
each separate science, and his suggestions as to 
how the "deficiencies" in the literature, learning, 
and science of his age might be supplied. But 
whatever was his own estimate of it, Diderot and 
D'Alembert believed that they could not do better 
than, in the main, adopt it as the basis of the 
French Encyclopaedia. "If we emerge from this 
vast operation," wrote the former of these authors 
in the Prospectus, " we shall owe it mainly to the 
chancellor Bacon, who sketched the plan of an 
universal dictionary of sciences and arts at a 
time when there were not, so to speak, either 
arts or sciences. This extraordinary genius, when 
it was impossible to write a history of what men 
already knew, wrote one of that which they had 
to learn." A circumstance so remarkable as that 
the famous French Encyclopaedists of the eighteenth 
century should derive from Bacon's scheme the 
plan and guiding principles of their gigantic work 



106 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

has naturally of itself drawn much attention to 
that scheme. 

It is a scheme which rests, as I have already 
observed, on a subjective foundation. Its basis 
is a division of the faculties of the rational soul. 
These, according to Bacon, are three, — Memory, 
Imagination, and Reason. "The sense, which is 
the door of the intellect, is affected by individual 
objects only. The images of those individuals — 
that is, the impressions received by the sense — 
are fixed in the memory, and pass into it, in the 
first instance, entire as it were, just as they occur. 
These the human mind proceeds to review and 
ruminate on ; and, thereupon, either simply 
rehearses them, or makes fanciful imitations of 
them, or analyses and classifies them. Therefore 
from these three fountains — Memory, Imagination, 
and Reason — flow these three emanations — History, 
Poesy, and Philosophy; and there can be no 
others." 

Memory, then, which accumulates facts, gives 
rise to History, which is either Natural or Civil 
—either of the works of nature or of the works 
of man. Natural History subdivides into the 
history of generations, of prseter-generations, and 
of the arts, since nature is, "(1) either free, 
proceeding in her ordinary course, without molest- 
ation; or (2) obstructed by some stubborn and 



CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 107 

less common matters, and thence put out of her 
course, as in the production of monsters; or (3) 
bound and wrought upon by human means, for 
the production of things artificial." Civil History, 
in general, subdivides into literary, sacred or eccle- 
siastical, and civil history strictly so called; the 
first treating of the progress of literature and 
learning, the second of the church, prophecy, 
and providence, and the third of the fortunes 
of states. 

Imagination operates on sensible materials, com- 
bining, magnifying, and idealising them at pleasure, 
and so gives rise to poetry, which, according to 
Bacon, is simply feigned history, verse being but 
a character of style. Poetry subdivides into — 

1. Narrative Poetry, " a mere imitation of history, 
such as might pass for real, only that it com- 
monly exaggerates things beyond probability"; 

2. Dramatic Poetry, "history made visible, for 
it represents actions as if they were present, 
whereas history represents them as past"; and 

3. Parabolical Poetry, "typical history, by which 
ideas that are objects of the intellect are rep- 
resented in forms that are objects of the sense." 

Reason operates on things by analysis and 
classification, by abstraction and generalisation, 
and so produces philosophy. But philosophy is 
not inclusive of all science; it must be distin- 



108 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

guished from the knowledge due to revelation — 
from theology. Theology descends from heaven, 
philosophy springs from the earth; theology is 
derived from divine inspiration, philosophy from 
external sense. At the same time, the knowledge 
based on revelation may be distributed in the 
same way as that based on natural perception. 
" Nor do I think that any other division is wanted 
for Theology. The information derived from rev- 
elation and the information derived from the sense 
differ, no doubt, both in the matter and in the 
mode of conveyance; but the human mind is the 
same, and its repositories and cells the same. It 
is only as if different liquids were poured through 
different funnels into one and the same vessel. 
Theology therefore consists either of Sacred History 
or of Parables, which are a divine poesy, or of 
Doctrines and Precepts, which are a perennial 
philosophy. For as for that part which seems 
supernumerary, namely, Prophecy, it is but a kind 
of history : for divine history has this prerogative 
over human, that the narration may be before 
the event as well as after." 
Divi«on The first division of the sciences, according to 
Theology Bacon, is into Theology and Philosophy; but in 
mdPha- Theology is not included Natural Theology, which 
is regarded as a part of Philosophy. " Philosophy," 
he says, " has three objects, viz., God, Nature, and 



CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 109 

Man; as also three kinds of rays — for Nature 
strikes the human intellect with a direct ray, God 
with a refracted ray, from the inequality of the 
medium betwixt the Creator and the creatures, and 
Man, as exhibited to himself, with a reflected ray : 
so that it is proper to divide Philosophy into the 
doctrine of the Deity, the Doctrine of Nature, and 
the doctrine of Man." These, then, are the main 
branches of philosophy, but the branches must join 
in a common trunk; the special sciences must di- 
verge out of a general science, consisting of the 
axioms common to several or to all of the other 
sciences, and including an inquiry into " transcend- 
ental, or the adventitious conditions of beings." 
This general science Bacon would name Primary Primary 

Phil* 

Philosophy. " As the divisions of the sciences are ^phy. 
not like different lines that meet in one angle, but 
rather like the branches of trees that join in one 
trunk, it is first necessary that we constitute an 
universal science as a parent to the rest, and as 
making a part of the common road to the sciences 
before the ways separate. And this knowledge we 
call philosophia prima, primary or summary phil- 
osophy ; it has no other for its opposite, and differs 
from other sciences rather in the limits whereby it 
is confined than in the subject as treating only the 
summits of things." 

The doctrine of Deity or Natural Theology Bacon 



110 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

SuMivi- does not subdivide. The doctrine of Nature or 

nous of 

Natural Natural Philosophy he first separates into Specu- 
<*ophy. lative and Practical; then, subdivides the specu- 
lative branch into Physics and Metaphysics — the 
one the investigation of efficient causes and matter, 
the other of final causes and form ; and the practical 
branch into Mechanics, and what he calls Magic, 
which answers in some measure to Experimental 
Science. To Natural Philosophy, Speculative and 
Practical, he adds Mathematics, Pure and Applied, 
but merely as an appendix, not as an independent 
science or distinct division of the sciences. 
Human The doctrine of Man he divides into Human and 
Phii- Civil Philosophy. Human Philosophy he distri- 
080p 7 ' butes into a doctrine of the body, a doctrine of the 
soul, and a doctrine of the things common to the 
body and the soul. The doctrine of the body is to 
be divided according to the goods of the body, and 
therefore comprises four sciences — Medicine, which 
aims at health; Cosmetic, which has regard to 
beauty ; Athletic, which looks to strength ; and 
Voluptuary, what Tacitus calls "eruditus luxus," 
which is conversant with pleasure. The doctrine of 
the soul comprehends the doctrine of the Substance 
of the Soul and the doctrine of the Faculties of 
the Soul, and the latter again includes Logic and 
Ethic ; the one treating of the understanding and 
reason, and the other of the will and affections. 



CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. Ill 

Civil Philosophy he divides into the Art of Con- 
versation, the Art of Negotiation, and the Art of 
State Policy. 

The Baconian scheme of classification is now Criticism 
before us. We do not overlook its many incidental un cimm- 
merits, although we require to confine ourselves to fication - 
the rapid indication of its chief defects. The main 
objection to it, as has been often pointed out, is the 
character of its fundamental principle. The rational 
soul does not exercise memory, imagination, reason, 
so much apart, or in as isolated a manner as is 
assumed, but together, so that all these faculties 
co-operate in every department of intellectual 
activity. Take history as the example. Not even 
in its lowest form is it a mere product of memory ; 
not even in the case of the most stupid historian is 
it a mere recollection of facts, but a record of facts 
selected according to certain real or supposed prin- 
ciples of reason. In a higher form, when it aims to 
reproduce the life of the past, it involves the most 
difficult and delicate exercise of imagination ; and in 
its highest form, the form of philosophical history, 
it requires a most comprehensive combination of 
mental gifts, and one in which mere memory is very 
subordinate to reason. Further, history and poetry 
neither admit of entire separation from science nor 
of distinct co-ordination with it. They are on a 



112 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

different level from science, and may both be 
covered by science. There is a science of history. 
Every fact of every kind of history requires to be 
explained, — that is, to be brought under the domain 
of science. Historical knowledge is knowledge' on 
the road to scientific knowledge. The perfect hist- 
ory of anything, the complete exhibition of what, 
how, and why anything is, must be also the science 
of that thing. In like manner, poetry in all its 
forms, imagination in all its workings, art in all its 
varieties and developments, conform to laws and are 
explicable by reason, and consequently are subjects 
of science. There is a science, philosophy, or doc- 
trine of the Fine Arts. ^Esthetic is the common 
name for it. 

As to the distribution of science, properly so 
called, there is obviously much that is arbitrary in 
Bacon's scheme. Theology is separated from Phil- 
osophy with a sharpness and absoluteness for which 
there is no sufficient warrant. Revelation may pro- 
ceed from divine inspiration, but theological science 
must be built up on adequately evidenced facts, and 
by strictly rational processes, even when its facts 
have their source in revelation and inspiration. 
The great mass of the facts recorded and of the 
truths stated in the writings which Christians 
accept as embodying a revelation, are facts of 
history and truths accessible to reason ; only a 



CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 113 

very small percentage of them can be exclusively 
referred to special inspiration. Philosophy cannot 
admit, consistently with loyalty to reason, that 
theology is outside of its domain. The separation 
of natural theology from other theology is the 
separation of a foundation from the edifice which 
it supports. Then, the threefold division of philo- 
sophy into the doctrine of Deity, of Nature, and of 
Man is unsatisfactory, requiring, for example, the 
body of man to have a science to itself widely 
distinct from the science which studies the bodies 
of other animals. It implies that the physiology of 
the human body is more related to psychology than 
to general physiology. The bringing together of 
Physics and Metaphysics as both parts of Natural 
Philosophy is another error which needs no refuta- 
tion at the present day ; the representing of Mathe- 
matics as a mere appendix to Natural Philosophy 
does so still less. The view given of the relation of 
Logic and Ethics, although at first sight plausible, 
will be found on examination untenable. 

The state of knowledge in Bacon's age can prob- Aiated's 
ably be more fully and distinctly learned from the j^L/ 
Encyclopedias of John Henry Alsted than from 
any other works. The first appeared as a quarto 
volume of upwards of three thousand pages in 1620; 
and the second, considerably more elaborate, in two 

H 



114 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

large folio volumes in 1630. Alsted was a clear- 
headed, learned, logical person, skilful in schematis- 
ing knowledge, indefatigable in composing com- 
pends, and his Encyclopedia of 1630 was a highly 
creditable production both in regard to matter and 
arrangement. By its rigidly methodical character 
it is no mere dictionary of arts and sciences, but 
entitled to the name of encyclopaedia, as few so- 
called encyclopaedias have been. It consists of 
thirty-five books. The first four are preliminary, 
treating of the intellectual habits involved in the 
acquisition of learning, the characteristics, order, 
and divisions of the various departments of know- 
ledge, and the ends and methods of study, its aids, 
hindrances, &c. The six books which follow deal, 
under the general heading of Philology, with Lexi- 
cology, Grammar, Rhetoric, Logic, the Art of 
Oratory, and Poetic. Philosophy is divided into 
Theoretical and Practical. Theoretical Philosophy 
has ten books devoted to it, since it includes ten 
sciences : Metaphysics, Pneumatics, Physics, Arith- 
metic, Geometry, Cosmography, Uranometry, Geog- 
raphy, Optics, and Music ; Practical Philosophy 
four books, because it comprehends the four sciences 
of Ethics, Economics, Politics, and Scholastic. In 
the three following books the three " Faculties," of 
Theology, Jurisprudence, and Medicine, are the 
subjects of dissertation. Theology is distributed 



CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 115 

into (1) Natural, (2) Catechetic, (3) Didactic, (4) 
Polemic, (5) Casuistic, (6) Prophetic, and (7) Moral; 
Jurisprudence into (1) General Civil, (2) Special 
Civil, and (3) Ecclesiastical : and Medicine in a way 
requiring more space than we can afford to describe. 
The three next books give an account of the 
mechanical arts. The last seven books are miscel- 
laneous and supplementary : prsecipuae farragines 
disciplinarum : mnemonica, historica, chronologia, 
architectonica, critica, &c. 

From the Instauratio Magna of Bacon the Comenius. 
great Moravian educational reformer, John Amos 
Comenius (1592-1671), derived the conviction that 
universal wisdom — the sum of all science — might 
be so arranged and presented that it could be 
acquired without difficulty by any ingenuous and 
intelligent youth. This belief in the attainability of 
a Christian pansophy — of an encyclopaedic culture 
which would surely, easily, and solidly lead up, step 
by step, from the most obvious facts of sense to the 
secret things of God revealed through Christ — was 
one of the chief inspiring motives to those labours 
which have made his name for ever immortal. The 
aim of his life was to show how his ideal could be 
realised by means of pansophic schools and pan- 
sophic universities. He expounded his conceptions 
in the Didactica magna, Prodromus pansophia, 
ScholoB philosophies delineatio, and other writings 



116 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

contained in his Opera didactica omnia, 4 vols., 
Amst., 1657. The reader will find an excellent 
account of what is essential and of abiding interest 
in these works in the John Amos Comenius of Pro- 
fessor Laurie of Edinburgh. Comenius' sketch of a 
pansophic university is reproduced by Professor 
Laurie in the following words : " As all knowledge 
was to lead to God, and to God as revealed through 
Christ, Comenius spoke of his encyclopsedism as a 
Christian Pansophy, and gave the * special titles of 
the seven parts of the temple of Christian Pansophy.' 
The first was to show the necessity and possibility 
of the temple and to give its external structure or 
outline — to be called the Templi Sapientice Pro- 
pylceum. The second part was to give the first 
approach to a knowledge of all knowable things — a 
general apparatus of wisdom — in which the highest 
genera and fundamental principles and axioms were 
to be exhibited, from which, as the primal sources of 
truth, the streams of all sciences flow and diverge — 
to be called the Porta. The third part (the primum 
Atrium) was to exhaust visible nature. The fourth 
(the Atrium medium) was to treat of man and 
reason ; the fifth part (Atrium internum), of man's 
essential nature — free-will and responsibility, and 
the repair of man's will in Christ as the beginning 
of the spiritual life. The sixth part (Sanctum 
sanctorum) was to be theological, and here man 



CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE 8CIENCES. 117 

was to be admitted to the study and worship of 
God and his revelation, that thereby he might be 
led to embrace God as the centre of eternal life. 
The seventh part (Fans aquarum viventium) was 
to expound the use of true wisdom and its dis- 
semination, so that the whole world might be filled 
with a knowledge of God " (pp. 72, 73). 

Comenius in the last period of his life yielded to w«geL 
the seductions of mysticism. Another religious en- 
cyclopaedist or pansophist, Erhard Weigel (1625- 
1699), went much farther in the same direction. He 
was a proficient in mathematical science and fancied 
that everything must be explained mathematically. 
He became a mystic through his excessive trust in 
the powers of mathematics, and hence while a mystic 
he was also a precursor of the Wolfian philosophical 
rationalism. The conception of philosophy as the 
universal science, and that all philosophy ought 
accordingly to be treated by the methods of mathe- 
matics, is fundamental in his Idea totius encyclo- 
paedias, Universi corporis pansophici prodromus de 
gradibus humancB cognitionis, Eihica Euelidea, and 
other works. The organisation of knowledge pro- 
posed by Comenius was made with a view to the 
practical requirements of teaching, and that proposed 
by Weigel was meant to confirm and illustrate a 
narrow conception of the nature of scientific method. 
It was not to be expected, therefore, that either 



118 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

scheme should have much value in the way of in- 
dicating the real relationships of the sciences. 

Hobbes. The greatest English philosophical contemporary 
of Bacon, Thomas Hobbes, also attempted a classi- 
fication of the sciences, and his classification, although 
it has been little remarked, is, in reality, very re- 
markable. While Hobbes had not the philosophical 
breadth or general wealth of mind characteristic of 
Bacon, he had far more analytic keenness and 
subtility, far more deductive vigour and self- con- 
sistency, and, in a word, decidedly greater specially 
scientific capacity. In spite of his dogmatic one- 
sidedness, few English thinkers have surpassed him 
in energy or range of intellect in the departments in 
which his strength chiefly lay. His scheme of the 
distribution and co-ordination of the sciences is ex- 
hibited with characteristic conciseness and precision 
in ch. 9 of Leviathan (1651). 

Two philosophical theories mould and control it 
from commencement to close, — sensationalism and 
nominalism, — of both of which Hobbes was one of 
the most strenuous and thoroughgoing advocates. 
Knowledge, he says, is of two kinds, — of facts and of 
the consequences of one affirmation to another. The 
knowledge of facts gives rise to history, and history 
is either natural history or civil history. The know- 
ledge of consequences gives rise to science, which 



CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 119 

is manifold according to the diversity of matters con- 
sidered. Its primary division is into Natural Philo- 
sophy and Civil Philosophy, according as conse- 
quences are from the accidents of bodies natural 
or of bodies politic. 

Natural Philosophy is, in its turn, divided in a 
twofold manner, according as the consequences of 
which it consists are drawn from the accidents 
common to all bodies, which are quantity and 
motion, or from the qualities of bodies. Conse- 
quences from quantity and motion indeterminate 
constitute Primary Philosophy ; from quantity and 
motion determined by figure, Geometry; from 
quantity and motion determined by number, Arith- 
metic ; from quantity and motion of bodies in special, 
if the larger parts of the world, as the earth and 
stars, Geography and Astronomy ; for special kinds 
of motions and special figures of bodies, Engineer- 
ing, Architecture, Navigation, &c. Then, going back 
to physics or consequences from the qualities of 
bodies natural, these consequences are either from 
the qualities of bodies transient, such as some- 
times appear and sometimes vanish, whence Meteor- 
ology ; or from the qualities of bodies permanent. 
Among permanent bodies are the stars, whence 
Sciography conversant with their light, and Astro- 
logy conversant with their influences ; the ether, 
whence a science of atmospheric fluids; terrestial 



120 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

bodies, which are either non-sentient or sentient. 
Consequences drawn from parts of the earth without 
sense are Mineralogy and Botany : the one con- 
versant with the qualities of minerals, and the other 
with the qualities of plants. Consequences from the 
qualities of animals are either of animals in general 
or men in special. If of animals in general, Optics 
is knowledge of consequences from vision; Music 
of consequences from sound; and some unnamed 
science or sciences of consequences from the rest of 
the senses. If of men in special, then, knowledge of 
consequences from the passions is Ethics ; from 
speech in magnifying, vilifying, &c., Poetry; in 
persuading, Rhetoric; in reasoning, Logic; in con- 
tracting, the Science of Just and Unjust. 

Civil Philosophy Hobbes did not subdivide into 
more special sciences. He supposed it to be largely 
his own creation, and that its history might be said 
to have begun with the publication of his De Cive 
(1646). 

Thus it was that Hobbes, with clear and sys- 
tematic genius, mapped out the various provinces 
of science. The praise of ingenuity and consider- 
able truthfulness cannot reasonably be denied to 
his arrangement. It shows a deeper and truer 
insight into the relations of the physical sciences 
than the chart of Bacon. At the same time, it 
is not difficult to see defects in it. Some of 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 121 

these, as, for instance, the absence of psychological 
science, might be supplied without any alteration 
of the principles on which it proceeds. Others 
are irremediable, resulting from those principles 
themselves. Of this character is the exclusion — 
deliberate exclusion, not simply omission — of theo- 
logical science. Hobbes maintained there could be 
no such science, on the ground that there could be 
no ideas except of the finite and contingent — that 
body or matter is alone intelligible; that spirit, 
being beyond the range of experiment and sense, is 
beyond comprehension, outside of the domain of 
science. His philosophy was essentially incom- 
patible with a recognition of the existence of theo- 
logical science. 

The strange and arbitrary way in which Hobbes 
in his classification deals with moral science may 
also be noted. Ethics is plainly united in the closest 
manner with Politics, and yet he separates Politics, 
under the name of Civil Philosophy, from Ethics, by 
almost as great a distance as his scheme allows. 
Civil Philosophy stands by itself — isolated, as the 
counterpart of Natural Philosophy — and Ethics is 
made a branch, or rather twig, of Natural Philosophy. 
Nor is this all ; but Ethics, as a science conversant 
about the passions, is separated from the Science of 
Just and Unjust, and this last, Hobbes, pushing his 
nominalism to the utmost, represents as a purely 



122 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

verbal science, since, according to him, contracts are 
the origin or ground of just and unjust. 

Locke. The last chapter of John Locke's Essay concerning 

Human Understanding (1690) treats "of the divi- 
sion of the sciences." Locke rightly judged that the 
consideration of that subject would be a fitting con- 
clusion to such an inquiry into the origin and nature 
of knowledge as he had instituted. It is only to be 
regretted that the consideration given was but slight 
and superficial. The division adopted was threefold 
— Physica, Practica, Semeiotica — "for a man can 
employ his thoughts about nothing, but either the 
contemplation of things themselves for the discovery 
of truth ; or about the things in his own power, 
which are his own actions, for the attainment of his 
own ends ; or the signs the mind makes use of both 
in the one and the other, and the right ordering of 
them for its clearer information." I. Physics, in the 
wide sense in which the term is used by Locke, is 
" the knowledge of things as they are in their own 
proper being, their constitution, properties, and opera- 
tions" ; it has for end bare speculative truth, " and 
whatsoever can afford the mind of man any such, 
falls under this branch, whether it be God himself, 
angels, spirits, bodies, or any of their affections." 
II. Practics is " the skill of right applying our own 
powers and actions, for the attainment of things good 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 123 

and useful. " Its chief branch is Ethics, " the seeking 
out those measures and rules of human actions which 
lead to happiness, and the means to practise them." 
III. Semeiotics is the doctrine of signs, and includes 
Logic, or the doctrine of words, "these being the 
signs which the mind makes use of for the under- 
standing of things, or conveying its knowledge to 
others." 

This division of science is much the same as that 
employed so long before by the Stoics. It has, 
however, even as presented by Locke, obvious and 
serious defects. Thus, for instance, the grouping 
together of all sciences the objects of which can be 
said to be " things," as distinct from " actions " and 
"signs," whatever be the characters otherwise of 
these .objects, and however great may be the differ- 
ences in the modes and methods in which they 
must be apprehended and studied, so far from being 
helpful towards a true correlation of the sciences, 
is productive of confusion which tends to render 
their correlation impossible. Further, either of the 
first two of Locke's groups includes the other two 
groups. Thus, if Physics comprehend a knowledge 
of man and of what pertains to man, it must 
embrace Semeiotics, which is conversant with man's 
reasoning and speech; and Practics, which is con- 
versant with his activities. So Practics would 
include all Physics, since whatever knowledge man 



124 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

can attain of Deity, nature, or his own mind, may 
be turned to use. Strictly speaking, indeed, 
Practics ought not to be regarded as a kind or 
branch of science, but as the application of science. 
The representation of Logic as merely a doctrine of 
signs may also be set down as erroneous. It implies 
an extreme of nominalism of which few will be 
found to approve. Further, as Dugald Stewart 
observes, "it is difficult to reconcile one's self to an 
arrangement which, while it classes with Astronomy, 
with Mechanics, with Optics, and with Hydrostatics, 
the strikingly contrasted studies of Natural Theology 
and the Philosophy of the Human Mind, disunites 
from the two last the far more congenial sciences of 
Ethic and Logic." In fact, Locke's discussion of 
the problem — " the division of the sciences " — is so 
inferior alike to Bacon's and to Hobbes' treatment 
of it that one can hardly suppose that he had read 
what they had written regarding it. 

Leibnis. Leibniz, in the last chapter of the Nouveaux 
Essais, criticised the classification of Locke, and 
easily succeeded, of course, in showing it to be 
radically defective. In particular, he urged with 
force the objection that each part of the division 
proposed might absorb the whole. He provided, 
however, no substitute for Locke's scheme. It does 
not help us to be told by him that the truths or 



CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 125 

doctrines of science may be arranged in three ways, 
viz.: (1) synthetically or theoretically, according to 
proofs ; (2) analytically or practically, according to 
ends ; and (3) lexically, according to letters or terms. 
What is wanted is an arrangement of the sciences, 
not of their parts. Only through the right defini- 
tion and division, constitution and correlation, of 
the sciences, can their parts, their component truths 
or doctrines, be scientifically arranged. Besides, 
the objection which Leibniz urges against Locke's 
division of sciences applies equally to his own 
division of methods of arranging truths, if it be 
presented as the basis of a classification of truths. 
Any one of these methods is capable of including all 
truths. Only one of them can be employed at one 
time, and whichever method be preferred, the 
classification of truths which is to be in accordance 
with its principles will have to be made without any 
help having been afforded by Leibniz. 

In fact, Leibniz had no real sense of the im- 
portance or clear conception of the nature of the 
problem before him. Hence his nearest approach 
to a classification of the sciences is included in 
a plan for the catalogue of a library, — Idea Leib- 
nitiana Bibliothecce ordinandce contractior. Now, 
the classification of the sciences and the classi- 
fication of books are so far connected that a good 
classification of the sciences must be of consider- 



126 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

able use to one who wishes to classify books, and 
that a good catalogue raisonnee of books may well 
afford assistance to one who would classify the 
sciences; but the two classifications are neverthe- 
less essentially distinct. The classification of the 
sciences is a fundamental problem of philosophy, the 
first step toward the correlation of the sciences, and 
so toward the positive philosophy of the sciences ; 
the classification of books is merely a practical 
problem of very limited interest, the convenience 
of bookish people. The classification proposed by 
Leibniz is one of books, and therefore, like those of 
Brunet, Girard, Home, Lubbock, and the general 
plans of all classed catalogues, necessarily non- 
philosophical His classes are, — 1. Theology; 2. 
Jurisprudence; 3. Medicine; 4. Intellectual Phil- 
osophy, which is either Theoretical (Logic, Meta- 
physics, Pneumatics) or Practical (Ethics and 
Politics) ; 5. Mathematical Philosophy, which in- 
cludes not only Pure Mathematics, but Astronomy, 
Mechanics, and all sciences specially dependent on 
vigour of imagination ; 6. Physical Philosophy, com- 
prehending Physics Proper, Chemistry, Mineralogy, 
Botany, Zoology, and all sciences which rest on a 
knowledge of the things of sense ; 7. Philology ; 8. 
History; and 9. Miscellanies. According to this 
arrangement, all knowledge belonging to the three 
Faculties of Theology, Law, and Medicine is severed 



CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 127 

and separated from Philosophy or Science, Phil- 
ology, and History. Thus, to give only a single 
example, Ecclesiastical History is expressly with- 
drawn from History in order to be planted in 
Theology. Of course, this is most arbitrary and 
unnatural. It would be a mere waste of time, 
indeed, to discuss at length any scheme of classifi- 
cation in which the subject-matter is divided both 
according to ' Faculties ' and Sciences. 

The Italian philosopher, Giambattista Vico (1688- Vioo. 
1744), cannot be said to have proposed any new 
classification of the sciences, and yet ought not to 
be altogether ignored. In this, as in so many 
other regions of thought, his power of profound 
and prophetic vision revealed itself. He was the 
first to state and expound as a fundamental law 
of human development the truth which Comte is 
often credited with having discovered, but which he 
merely so exhibited as to secure the general recogni- 
tion of its importance, — the truth that the entire 
movement of society must correspond to that of 
knowledge, the preponderant factor of historical 
evolution being the growth of intelligence. This 
truth he laid down as the foundation of his New 
Science not less explicitly or confidently than 
Comte affirmed it as the basis of his Positive 
Philosophy. The order of social evolution accord- 



128 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

ing to Vico, as according to Comte, is a necessary 
order determined by the advance of reason. Hence, 
a law of three periods of history through which all 
sciences and arts, ideas and institutions, naturally 
pass. The periods are designated by Vico the 
Divine, the Heroic, and the Human, and the root 
of each is described by him as a peculiar mode of 
conception or form of wisdom. Therefore, he main- 
tains, there are three stages of science, three kinds 
of nature, three types of character, three epochs of 
religion, three species of language, of writing, of 
governments, of natural law, of jurisprudence, <fcc. 
Another equally original idea of his is entitled 
to be noted here. The "New Science" which he 
claimed to have founded he maintained to be the 
central and regulative science. He regarded his 
discovery of it as not merely an addition to the 
sciences, but a revolution in the whole system of 
the sciences, inasmuch as it showed that not 
metaphysics or physics, but the science of the 
development of the human mind in history was 
the fundamental and governing science. In his 
view the science of history was the most compre- 
hensive science, and all other sciences were rooted 
or included in it, and had their character and rank 
determined by their relationship to it. All science, 
he held, is the production of the human mind ; the 
whole science of any age is only a transient stage in 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 129 

the history of the human mind ; the perfect state of 
a science is but the last period of its history ; there- 
fore, the science of history is not merely a special 
and rather limited science, as we are apt to suppose, 
but an all-comprehensive science, the true science of 
the sciences. It is so because the fundamental, con- 
stitutive, and regulative principle of all science is not 
the abstract, transcendent, objective, but the actual, 
immanent, subjective — the all -productive reason. 
This was a singularly bold and luminous conception. 
To demonstrate its truth may be said to have been, 
consciously or unconsciously, the ultimate aim of all 
the labours of Kant, Fichte, Schelling, Hegel, and 
their followers. 1 

With Christian Wolff (1679-1754) and his school, Wolffi 
German philosophy passed into a stage of dogmatic 
rationalism. The general contents of the current 
philosophy and religion, the teachings of the special 
sciences, the leading principles and main tenets of 
Cartesianism, and the distinctive views of Leibniz 
with certain modifications, were attempted to be 
systematised and demonstrated by logical deduction 
of a mathematical rigour and certainty. Wolffian- 
ism was essentially encyclopaedic. It sought to 
include and absorb all science. And yet it was 

1 See the author's Vico in Blackwood's "Philosophical Classics." 
The book has been translated into Italian. 



130 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE 8CIENCES. 

thoroughly one-sided. It ignored the fact that the 
methods of science must vary with the objects of 
science; that each science must have its own 
appropriate modifications of method; that an ade- 
quate philosophy can recognise no uniform universal 
method. It was one-sided also in this respect, that 
it confounded philosophy with the special sciences. 
It represented the special sciences as simply sections 
of philosophy. That is an error so radical as to 
make unnecessary any other criticism of the Wolffian 
classification. 

Wolff distributes knowledge into historical, mathe- 
matical, and philosophical. Philosophy he divides 
into two great departments corresponding to two 
fundamental faculties of the soul, — Metaphysics to 
a facultas cognoscitiva and Practical Philosophy to 
a facultas appetitiva. At the same time he treats 
Logic — chiefly, however, on educational grounds — 
as antecedent and preparatory to both Metaphysics 
and Practical Philosophy. In Metaphysics he 
includes Ontology, Cosmology, Psychology, and 
Natural Theology. These sciences he regards as 
following in natural order from more general and 
simple to more special and complex. In Practical 
Philosophy he includes Ethics, Economics, and 
Politics. His follower Baumgarten did good service 
by vindicating the right of ^Esthetics to a place by 
the side of Ethics. 

The Wolffian philosophy was followed by a so- 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THB SCIENCES. 131 

called " Popular Philosophy," which was a con- 
tinuation of its rationalism, but a reaction from 
its formalism. The period of the prevalence of 
this Popular Philosophy was one in which great 
desire was shown to make the acquisition of science 
easy. It accordingly abounded in " Introductions," 
" Outlines," and " Methods." It was a period in 
which even special Encyclopaedias — Encyclopaedias 
of particular departments of knowledge, e.g., Ency- 
clopaedias of Theology — began to appear. It was 
also the period when the want of a propaedeutic to 
the study of the sciences made itself so strongly 
felt as to give rise to the conception of a special 
science for its satisfaction and to various attempts 
to construct such a science; the period in which 
Gesner, Schade, Mertens, and others sought to raise 
what they called Hodegetic or Isagogic to the rank 
of a separate and fundamental discipline. It was, 
above all, the period in which the idea of the organic 
unity, diversity, and interrelationism of the sciences 
obtained a universality and clearness of recognition 
which it had never previously received, although it 
had at no time since Plato gave it magnificent 
expression been entirely ignored. It was not, how- 
ever, a period in which philosophical problems were 
investigated with depth or thoroughness. As to 
the problem even of which we are tracing the 
history it cannot be said to have produced any 
solution of much value. 



132 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 



III. FROM KANT TO DE TRACY. 

Kant. Immanuel Kant (1724-1804), by the publication 

of his Critique of Pure Reason, inaugurated a new 
and great epoch of philosophy — a philosophy which 
has had an enormous influence on the higher 
thought of mankind. He also treated expressly of 
the very subject we are dealing with, a classifica- 
tion of the sciences, in the chapter of his Critique 
headed " The Architectonic of Pure Reason," and 
has left elsewhere in his writings various passages 
supplementary to the views expressed by him in 
that chapter. He is not therefore to be here 
ignored. Neither is there, however, any good 
reason why he should have a large place in any 
account of a history of our subject. 

Science is regarded by Kant as an organism 
which grows from within, not an aggregate which 
increases from without. A science, according to 
Kant, is a system of conceptions unified and dis- 
tributed by a central and regulative idea; or, in 
other words, a system organised on what he calls 
architectonic principles, or constituted by parts 
which possess an essential affinity and can be de- 
duced from one supreme and internal aim. The 
idea out of which a science is developed — which is 
the condition of its possibility, and which deter- 



CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 133 

mines its form and end — is a constituent element 
of reason; and hence not only is each science a 
unity in itself, but all sciences are related as parts 
of one grand system of knowledge. Knowledge is 
either rational or empirical. Rational knowledge is 
based either on conceptions or on the construction 
of conceptions. In the former case it is philosophy, 
in the latter mathematics. Philosophy is either a 
criticism of the powers of reason, Critical Philos- 
ophy, or a systematic presentation of the truths 
given by pure reason, Metaphysic. Metaphysic, 
again, is either of the speculative or of the practical 
reason — either a metaphysic of nature or a meta- 
physic of ethics. The metaphysic of nature divides 
into two parts — Transcendental Philosophy and 
Rational Physiology. The former, which may be 
also called Ontology, presents the system of all the 
conceptions and principles belonging to the under- 
standing and reason which relate to objects in 
general, but not to any particular given objects; 
the latter has nature or the sum of given objects for 
its subject-matter, and is either immanent or tran- 
scendent. Immanent Physiology considers nature 
as the sum of the objects of experience presented 
according to a priori conditions ; and when these 
objects are those of the external senses it is Rational 
Physics, when those of internal sense, Rational Psy- 
chology. Transcendental Physiology, on the other 



134 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

hand, relates to connections of nature which take 
us beyond all possible experience, and is, when it 
embraces nature as a whole, Rational Cosmology, 
and when it views nature in connection with a 
Being above nature, Rational Theology. Mathe- 
matics, Critical Philosophy, Ontology, Rational 
Physics, Rational Psychology, Rational Cosmology, 
Rational Theology, and the Metaphysic of Ethics 
are consequently the sciences of pure reason. Dis- 
tinct from, yet related to, Rational Physics and 
Rational Psychology are to be placed Empirical 
Physics and Empirical Psychology as parts of Ap- 
plied Philosophy, the a priori principles of which 
are contained in Pure Philosophy. 

This scheme of the sciences suggests various ob- 
jections. It is not a result of a direct study of the 
sciences and of their relations to one another, but a 
consequence of assent to a peculiar metaphysical 
theory. It is such as was to be expected from 
treating the problem involved at a wrong place and 
in a wrong way. The division of knowledge into 
rational and empirical is radically erroneous, for all 
knowledge is at once rational and empirical. There 
is no reason without experience, or experience with- 
out reason. That Kant knew this — that he was 
aware that reason entirely pure, altogether un- 
touched and unaffected by experience, is absolutely 
ignorant and inactive, and that experience is only 



CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 135 

constituted by the synthetic activity of reason — far 
from excusing, is precisely what makes inexcusable 
his opposing and contrasting, as he does here, reason 
and experience, rational and empirical knowledge. 
The division of rational knowledge into Mathematics 
and Philosophy is as little to be commended. 
Mathematics is as subject to philosophy, as much 
comprehended within the sphere of philosophy, as 
any other science or group of sciences. Philosophy 
has to deal with the construction of conceptions as 
well as with conceptions themselves, for it has to 
treat of the methods of science not less than of its 
principles. It is universal science. Then, the place 
which Kant gives to Metaphysic is quite exorbitant 
and extravagant. In fact, he assigns to it and 
Mathematics the whole world of science, properly 
so called. Pure thought — thought which may have 
a relation to experience, but borrows nothing from 
it — is represented as able to establish and con- 
struct all science worthy of the name, and like- 
wise to lend out of its fulness to empirical studies 
the principles which alone give them a sort of delu- 
sive appearance of science. But neither Kant nor 
any one else has demonstrated that reason has such 
a strength and wealth of power, or is more than a 
faculty or mental instrument of discovering truth 
about the universe in and through experience. 
During the latter half of the eighteenth century 



136 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

there were, as already indicated, owing to the in- 
fluence of Wolffianism, Kantianism, and the Auf- 
klarung, a considerable number of attempts made 
by German authors to give easily intelligible ency- 
clopaedic surveys of the whole field of science. 

Suker. J. G. Sulzer was one of the most highly appre- 

ciated German authors of his day. His Short Sum- 
mary of all Sciences mentioned above was not un- 
worthy of his reputation. It was, however, of far 
less importance than his General Theory of the Fine 
Arts (Allgemeine Theorie der Schonen Kunste) y 
first announced in 1760, and published only in 1771- 
74. Baumgarten, it is true, by the publication of 
his JSsthetica (2 vols., 1750 and 1759), preceded 
him, and had the honour of first adding ^Esthetics 
to the list of the sciences. A scarcely less honour, 
however, seems to have been due to Sulzer, as his 
work apparently was the first in which there was 
given a comprehensive view of the fine arts (literary 
included) in their various relationships. For more 
than half a century he was considered in Germany 
the chief authority in aesthetics, and that even by 
those who differed from him in important respects. 
Sir William Hamilton, to the close of his profes- 
sional career, and while criticising the psychological 
basis of Sulzer's views on aesthetics, acknowledged 
those views to be the best he was acquainted with, 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 137 

his own and Aristotle's excepted. 1 Yet the author 
of a generally able and admirable History of 
^Esthetic, Professor Bosanquet, has not once men- 
tioned in it even the name of Sulzer. That is surely 
a strange and large omission. In any general history 
of aesthetic Sulzer's contribution to the science of 
aesthetic, instead of being overlooked, ought to 
have a considerable and prominent place. The 
general distribution of the sciences proposed by 
Sulzer was one in which they were referred either 
to the faculty of knowledge or the faculty of 
feeling. The inadequacy of it for the purpose 
intended will now, in all probability, be univers- 
ally recognised. 

Gesner's Primary Lines of Introduction to all operand 
Learning, Meinecke's Synopsis of all Learning, ° **** 
Klugel's Encyclopedic Survey of the different 
kinds of Knowledge and Science, Roth's System 
of the kinds of Human Knowledge and Science, 
and Von Berg's Essay on the Foundations and 
all parts of Science, were all in their day well- 
appreciated works. Their authors felt themselves 
to have a mission, endeavoured not unsuccess- 
fully to write with clearness and simplicity, and 
largely contributed to diffuse throughout Germany 
desire for a many-sided culture. While aiming, 
however, at an encyclopaedic knowledge they 

1 Metaphysics, voL ii. pp. 467-471. 



138 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THB SCIENCES. 

arrived at no satisfactory classification or co- 
ordination of the sciences. 

Krug. W. T. Krug (1770-1842) was an even more 

influential author than any of those just men- 
tioned. He had carefully studied the philosophies 
of both Wolff and Kant without making any sur- 
render of his own independence of mind. And 
although he did more than any one else to 
popularise many of the views of the latter, he 
freely criticised others, and is justly enough classed 
as only a Semi-Kantian. He was acknowledged to 
have a very wide acquaintance with almost all the 
recognised sciences. As regards the fundamental 
science of Logic, his opinions were both more 
accurate and more advanced than those of Kant 
himself, a fact which may so far explain why Sir 
Wm. Hamilton in his Lectures on Logic made far 
longer and more numerous quotations from him 
than from Kant, or indeed from any other logician 
except Aristotle. Although not so ingenious or 
profound as Kant, he was very worthy of the 
successorship to his chair. I have thus far men- 
tioned only his 'Lecture' (Vorlesung) of 1795, as 
it only had appeared early enough to be in the 
eighteenth century. A mere 'Lecture/ however, 
could only be of slight value in comparison with 
his Outline of a New Organon of Philosophy 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 139 

(1801), his Handbook of Philosophy (1803), and 
his magnum opus, his Universal Handbook of the 
Philosophical Sciences (5 vols. 1827). Hence I 
must in this case cross the boundary between two 
centuries in order to be able to state what his 
classification of the sciences was, as it is only on 
the hither side of the line, only in the later works 
mentioned, that the scheme was elaborated. I shall 
do no more, however, than merely state the abstract 
and general result, — the bare scheme itself. It was 
as follows : — 

The Sciences are either Free or Natural, Bound 
or Positive, or Mixed. 

A. The Free or Natural Sciences are formed 
solely by the free activity of the human mind, 
and are reducible to three general groups : — 

1. The Empirical, divisible into (a) Philo- 

logical and (6) Historical Sciences; 

2. The Rational, comprehending (a) Mathe- 

matical and (6) Philosophical Sciences; 
and 

3. The Empirico- Rational, which is either 

(a) Anthropological or (6) Physical 
Science. 

B. The Bound or Positive Sciences are depen- 
dent on authority, and fall into two groups: — 

1. The Positive Theological Sciences, and 

2. The Positive Juridical Sciences. 



140 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

C. The Mixed Sciences are those which are 
theoretically free, but practically and in appli- 
cation subject to and controlled by authority. 
They comprise — 

1. The Politico-Economical, and 

2. The Medical Sciences. 

Such was the scheme of classification of the sciences 
ultimately arrived at by Krug. Presented as it 
necessarily is here, i.e., as a skeleton in all its bare- 
ness, it must seem to have little if anything to 
recommend it. On the contrary, grave objections 
to it must make themselves felt. One is that no 
sciences are formed solely by the free activity of the 
human mind. All of them are to a large extent 
dependent on the nature of the objects on which free 
human activity is exercised. Another objection is 
that no true sciences, either theological or juridical, 
are bound or positive in the sense of being dependent 
on authority. In so far as they are so treated they 
cannot be truly sciences. The free exercise of 
rational activity is inseparable from all true science. 
It holds good of what Krug calls the Mixed Sciences 
no less than of those which he represents as Bound 
or Positive Sciences. Only in so far as Political 
Economy and Medical Studies are free can they be 
truly sciences, and what is true of them is just as 
true of Theology and Jurisprudence and all other 
studies or sciences. In all genuine study science 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 141 

and philosophy, truth and freedom, are inseparable. 
Notwithstanding these remarks I should greatly 
regret were any one to infer from them that the 
works in which Krug's scheme of classification is 
imbedded are unworthy of study. They are very 
much the reverse. 

In the latter half of the eighteenth century there Encycio- 
was nowhere shown so strong a desire for encycio- efforts, 
paedic views of the sciences as in Germany. Our 
English freethinkers of that time showed little 
interest in the study of scientific or speculative 
problems. Yet even then England had a Cyclopaedia, 
of a kind now well known and fully appreciated, 
prior to any other country. I refer to the English 
Cyclopaedia compiled and edited by Ephraim Cham- 
bers. It appeared first in 1728, then in 1738, and 
next in 1739, — the later editions being greatly 
enlarged by supplementary volumes. It was trans- 
lated into French and Italian, originated Cyclopaedias 
in all other European countries, and in England 
became the basis of the greatly extended work of 
Dr Eees, published in 45 vols. (1802-19). The 
most widely famed and politically influential of 
Encylopaedias was the French Encyclopidie, ou Dic- 
tionnaire raisonnS des sciences, arts et metiers, par 
une sociStS des gens de lettres (17 torn, fol., 1751-65). 
Its two leading contributors were D'Alembert and 



142 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

Diderot, both highly gifted men, the former a great 
proficient in mathematics and physics, and the latter 
endowed with wonderful readiness of thought and 
mastery of exposition on any subject. The Dw- 
cours prSliminaire was the work of D'Alembert, 
the article on EncyclopSdie of Diderot, and the 
Prospectus (afterwards incorporated in the Discours 
pr&iminaire) of both. In the Prospectus the plan 
of Chambers is admitted to be excellent but the 
execution is said to be very indifferent. The plan, 
indeed, alike of Chambers and of D'Alembert and 
Diderot, was mainly borrowed from Bacon. Neces- 
sarily the French Encyclopedic with its large SocUt6 
des gens de lettres was much superior in execution 
to the English Encyclopedia, which was almost the 
work of one man. 

iyAiem- D'Alembert was unfortunate when he adopted 
the Baconian scheme of classification as the founda- 
tion of his own. The chief alterations made by 
him on it in his Preliminary Discourse have been 
well indicated by Prof. Fowler in the following 
passage (Francis Bacon, pp. 75, 76): "The places 
of Imagination and Reason, Poetry and Philosophy, 
are reversed, so that in the scheme of the Encyclo- 
pedic Poetry comes last; the Imagination being 
regarded by D'Alembert as a more mature faculty 
(he is, of course, speaking of the creative, not of 
the merely reproductive Imagination) than the 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 143 

Reason, and posterior to it in the order of develop- 
ment. Revealed Theology, instead of being treated 
as co-ordinate with and distinct from Human 
Learning, is included under that part of Philosophy 
which is concerned with the knowledge of God, 
Natural Theology and the Science of evil spirits 
being the co-ordinate branches. Metaphysics is 
used in no less than three senses. In one sense, 
it stands at the head of Philosophy, and has a 
certain affinity to the Philosophia Prima of Bacon. 
In another sense, it is employed as the equivalent 
of Pneumatology, or the science of souls as distinct 
from bodies, and in this sense is called Particular 
Metaphysic. Finally, there is a metaphysic of 
bodies, or general physic, which treats of extent, 
movement, impenetrability, &c, or the properties 
common to all bodies. Mathematics is made one 
of the main divisions of the Philosophy of Nature, 
instead of a mere appendix, and the mathematical 
as well as the physical sciences are much more 
elaborately divided than in Bacon's classification. 
The various medical sciences, or those which have 
to do with the care of man's body, are classified 
on a more scientific basis, and transferred from 
the Philosophy of Man to the Philosophy of Nature. 
Morals are divided into general and particular: 
general ethics being concerned with discussions on 
the nature of good and evil, on the necessity of 
being virtuous, &c. : particular ethics with the 



144 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

special duties of the individual when regarded 
alone, of man in the family, and of man in society, 
denominated respectively Natural, Economical, and 
Political Jurisprudence, a similar division being 
applicable to the conduct of states. Poesy is not 
confined to Poetry proper, but is made coextensive 
with the Fine Arts in general " 

Those alterations of D'Alembert, however, neces- 
sarily failed to improve to any great extent a 
scheme so radically erroneous as Bacon's, — one of 
which the root-principle was the separation of three 
inseparable mental states or faculties. No advan- 
tage was gained, or could be gained, by reversing 
the places of Imagination and Eeason, Poetry and 
Philosophy, as was done by D'Alembert. His put- 
ting poetry after history and science, and repre- 
senting imagination as a more mature faculty than 
reason, was going farther astray than Bacon had 
done, and more inconsistent with the testimony 
of history and psychology. That poetry and art 
are posterior to history and science is not in accord- 
ance with known facts and with the real order of 
intellectual development. To assign historical 
studies and their products to memory alone has 
been already indicated to be erroneous. 

The division of history into sacred and secular, 
ecclesiastical and civil, although a very common 
one, is also a very misleading one. A history of 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 145 

mankind or the history of a nation is, or at least 
should be, as sacred and religious as a history of 
a church or churches. All history is sacred in so 
far as it is pervaded by the power and spirit of 
God. No clear, sharp, fixed distinction can be 
drawn between sacred and secular, ecclesiastical 
and civil. The larger or so-called civil society is, 
or at least may be, as well entitled to be deemed 
sacred and religious as the smaller and so-called 
ecclesiastical societies within it. The Old Testa- 
ment is throughout historical, but it certainly 
never represents history as divisible into sacred 
and secular, religious and political. There were 
no ecclesiastical denominations in apostolic times, 
and the New Testament ecclesia never means an 
ecclesiastical denomination. The ecclesia in its 
distinctively Scriptural sense is not a visible cor- 
poration at all, although it manifests itself in all 
spheres of human activity wherever there is the 
working of spiritual life. The kingdom of God 
which is so prominent in the New Testament is 
certainly not one in which Churchmen are described 
as having any exclusive or prominent place, but 
certainly one which from the New Testament point 
of view is as wide as history itself, because as wide 
as the whole providential and redemptive work of 
God as traceable in the history of mankind. 

Under the head of 'Memory' D'Alembert adds 



146 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

to ' Sacred ' and ' Civil ' History ' Natural History/ 
and gives a very elaborate distribution of its objects 
and of the uses to which they might be applied 
in arts, trades, and manufactures. This was an 
important addition to the Baconian scheme, — one 
most creditable to the editor (or editors) of the 
JEncyclop4die 9 and necessarily helpful to those who 
contributed to it. As 'History' is represented in 
the scheme to be related only to 'Memory/ so 
is 'Philosophy' to 'Reason.' Philosophy itself is 
subdivided into the Science of God, the Science 
of Man, and the Science of Nature. The first 
of these is represented as including Natural and 
Revealed Religion and the Science of Good and 
Evil Spirits, — a worse than worthless view, such 
as can hardly be regarded as a serious one. 

The Science of Man is divided into Logic and 
the Doctrine of Morality, and each of these again 
into Arts. The scheme is elaborate, but to a 
large extent artificial. The Science of Nature is 
identified with General Metaphysics, Ontology, or 
Science of Being in general, and divided into 
Mathematics and Physics. Mathematics again is 
divided into Pure and Mixed, and Physics into 
General, Particular, and Chemistry. Subdivision 
is carried still farther, and, indeed, too far. On 
the whole, however, the scheme of classification 
under the head of Philosophy must, with all its 



CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 147 

faults, be regarded as a very remarkable and 
valuable piece of work. It seems impossible to 
determine how far D'Alembert was aided by 
Diderot in the elaboration and exposition of 
it, but there can, I think, be little reasonable 
doubt that it must have been in the main the 
work of the former, the more scientific of the two 
men. 

Under the head of ' Imagination ' Poetry is 
divided into Sacred and Profane, then subdivided 
into Narrative, Dramatic, and Parabolic, and each 
of these subdivisions into others. But in that 
there seems to be no merit whatever. In fact, 
there is not a single science properly so-called 
included in the section 'Imagination.' The ex- 
tension given to the term 'Poesie' so as to make 
it coextensive with 'the Fine Arts in general* 
was a misapplication of it. Baumgarten had 
previously found the appropriate term for 'the 
Fine Arts in general/ — the term Aesthetik. 

The extraordinary philosophical activity to which 
Kant's critical investigations into the nature and 
foundations of knowledge gave rise early in the 
nineteenth century was applied much more to what 
was called the doctrine of science ( Wissenschafts- 
lehre) than to direct study of the sciences them- 
selves or of their relations to one another. Fichte, 
Schelling, Hegel, and their followers felt the neces- 



148 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

sity of giving to the fundamental problems as to the 
reality and validity of all that had been assumed to 
be knowledge better and more constructive solu- 
tions than those of Kant. Indeed his solutions 
seemed to them essentially destructive, and himself 
'der zermalmende/ — an even greater 'smasher' of 
all old theories and doctrines than the Scottish 
Hume. Hence they felt that their own work must 
necessarily be not only essentially critical but also 
essentially constructive, the discovery and proof of 
a fundamental philosophy or science of knowledge 
which could not be destroyed like the older theories 
and systems that Hume and Kant had discredited 
without finding for them any credible or adequate 
substitutes. The sciences properly so called could 
not fail to be influenced by the turn thus taken by 
speculative thought, nor could they fail to be to 
a large extent influenced to their disadvantage. 
Imagination and dreaming got inextricably com- 
bined and confused with reason and reality. The 
minds of the Teutonic philosophers of the time 
ceased to be conscious of the laws and limitations 
of human thought. The main result of that was an 
extraordinary activity in the formation of systems 
of belief based on some so-called science of know- 
ledge ( Wissenschaftshhre) of a thinker's own inven- 
tion and maintained by him to be the only true and 
correct standard of all kinds of knowledge. 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 149 

Fichte (1762-1814) led the way, and a singularly Fichte. 
gifted leader he was. He is certainly entitled to 
an eminent place in a history of the Doctrine 
of Science. He showed that pure Kantianism — 
Kantianism as taught by Kant himself — could not 
be rationally maintained owing to the self-con- 
tradictoriness pervading the whole system from 
beginning to end. With eagle glance he gazed, 
with eagle swoop he struck, straight at the quest- 
ion around which Kant floundered with whale-like 
awkwardness, What is the essential unifying factor 
in all knowledge and in all that is known? He 
saw that in Kant's teaching there was no such 
factor, and made it manifest not only that he 
himself but that Schelling, Hegel, and other 
eminent thinkers could not consistently rest in 
a teaching so radically inconsistent as was that of 
Kant. Hence Fichte must be adjudged entitled to 
an eminent place in a history of the doctrine of 
science or philosophy of knowledge. 

He has, however, no special claim to any such 
position in a history of the distribution or classifi- 
cation of the sciences. He was far from having as 
wide or accurate an acquaintance with any of the 
positive sciences as Kant, for example, had; and 
did little, if anything, in the way of showing how 
those sciences are related to one another and to the 
world of science as an intelligible whole. What he 



150 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

really did, or attempted to do, was to represent 
various kinds of knowledge or action as offshoots 
of the Wissenschaftslehre. It he held to be the 
fundamental philosophy on which all special studies 
should be based, to which they must be traced 
back, and by the spirit of which they should be 
permeated and vivified; and hence in his various 
writings he brought into connection with it such 
subjects as (1) Revelation, (2) Theoretical Philo- 
sophy, (3) Practical Philosophy, (4) Law of Nature, 
(5) Systematic Ethics, (6) Philosophy of History, 
&c. Indeed, he assumes or affirms all sciences to 
have their principles in the Science of Knowledge. 
That, however, does not yield a classification of the 
sciences. 

Schelling (1775-1854) has often been credited with 
having dealt with the subject under consideration in 
a rather effective manner, and, in particular, with 
having anticipated, if not suggested, the solution of 
it given by Comte. The following words of Morell 
have been frequently quoted with approval : " The 
influence of Schelling was not confined to Germany. 
His attempt to unite the process of the physical 
sciences in some affiliated line with the study of 
man, both in his individual constitution and historic 
development, has also had a very considerable result 
out of his own country. No one, for example, who 
compares the philosophic method of Schelling with 



CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIBNCE8. 151 

the ' Philosophic Positive ' of Auguste Comte can 
have the slightest hesitation as to the source from 
which the latter virtually sprang. The fundamental 
idea is, indeed, precisely the same as that of Schelling, 
with this difference only — that the idealistic language 
of the German speculator is here translated into the 
more ordinary language of physical science. That 
Comte borrowed his views from Schelling we can by 
no means affirm ; but that the whole conception of 
the affiliation of the sciences, in the order of their 
relative simplicity, and the expansion of the same 
law of development so as to include the exposition 
of human nature and the course of social progress, is 
all to be found there, no one in the smallest degree 
acquainted with Schelling's writings can seriously 
doubt." 1 

Since Morell thus wrote documentary evidence 
has come to light which proves that Comte could 
not possibly have borrowed from Schelling. It is 
unnecessary, however, to bring forward that evi- 
dence, seeing that the Comtist classification of the 
sciences has no real connection with the procedure 
of Schelling affirmed to be, in the main features, 
identical with it. Schelling's procedure is in no 
sense a classification of the sciences, and the prin- 
ciple of it is utterly antagonistic to that of Comte. 
Comte's principle is that of a methodical study of 

1 " Modern German Philosophy " ; Manchester Papers, 1856. 



152 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

phenomena. Schelling's is that of the self-movement 
and potentiation of the Absolute, from the lowest 
manifestation of so-called matter to the highest 
activity of reason. The method of Comte is that of 
science directly studied, generalised, and distributed. 
The method of Schelling is that of a high-soaring 
ontology. It is altogether illusory to compare the 
successive " potences " of Schelling with the funda- 
mental sciences of Comte. Yet it is only just to 
add that Schelling at all stages and in all phases of 
his theorising took a keen interest in the sciences, 
and wrote much of a very suggestive although 
not infrequently very dubious character. Many a 
scientist, I imagine, may read, for instance, with 
considerable pleasure and profit, the Lectures on the 
Method of Academic Study, published in 1803. 
The subjects treated of in them are the following : — 
1. The Absolute Idea of Science; 2. The Scientific 
and Ethical Functions of Universities ; 3. The 
Primary Presuppositions of a University Course of 
Study ; 4. The Study of the Pure Sciences of Reason, 
Mathematics, and General Philosophy; 5. The 
Ordinary Objections to the Study of Philosophy ; 
6. On the Special Study of Philosophy; 7. Upon 
some of the Departments which are to be discrim- 
inated from Philosophy — Specially the Positive 
Sciences ; 8. The Historical Construction of Christi- 
anity ; 9. The Study of Theology ; 10. The Study 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 153 

of History and Jurisprudence; 11. Natural His- 
tory; 12. Physics and Chemistry; 13. Medicine 
{Pathology) ; and 14. Philosophy of Art (^Esthetics). 
In his other numerous works he has so far treated 
of those subjects in relation to absolute science. 
Although his treatment of them leads neither to 
a tenable classification nor a satisfactory organisa- 
tion of the sciences, it has already been, and may 
perhaps still be, of some value to them. 

In the decade from 1806 to 1816 a number of dis- 
tributions and surveys of the sciences appeared in 
Germany. It may suffice merely to mention them. 
Hefter published, in 1806, a Philosophical Exposi- 
tion of a System of all Sciences ; Topfer, in the same 
year, a General Encyclopaedic Chart of all Sciences, 
to which he added, in 1808, a Commentary; Ortloff, 
in 1807, a Systematic Distribution of the Sciences, 
&c. ; Burdach, in 1809, an Organism of Human 
Science and Art; Simon, in 1810, a Tabular 
Survey of the Sciences; the celebrated Lorenz 
Oken, in 1809-11, a Handbook of the Philosophy 
of Nature (tr. by Tulk for the Ray Society) ; and 
Jasche, in 1816, an Introduction to an Architectonik 
of the Sciences. The works of the first five authors 
mentioned have quite passed into oblivion. Jasche 
is known chiefly as the editor of Kant's Logic. 
Oken is still recognised as a man of genius, but 



154 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

the scheme of science indicated in his Handbook 
has been generally found by those who tried to 
appreciate it as so original as to be unintelligible. 

Hegel Hegel, in 1817, exhibited, in his Encyclopedia 

of the Philosophical Sciences, a vast system of 
thought which he believed inclusive of all the 
fundamental sciences, and necessarily assigning to 
each of them its appropriate place in the organic 
and rational whole of knowledge. Judging his 
work even exclusively from the point of view 
which here specially concerns us, it must, I think, 
be pronounced a prodigious advance on those which 
preceded it, as any one may easily discover for him- 
self by comparing it with the best of the produc- 
tions mentioned in the previous paragraph. Hegel 
connects and groups the fundamental sciences in an 
order which is to a large extent true, and presents a 
very remarkable exemplification of a most magnifi- 
cent conception of a Science of the Sciences. He 
supposes that through the various stages of in- 
dividual and collective experience and activity 
described in the Phcenomenology of the Spirit, and 
in the "Introduction" to the Encyclopedia, con- 
sciousness is enabled to rise to absolute cognition, 
to knowledge of the thought which is all-originative 
and all-inclusive, to apprehension of the Idea which 
is the essence alike of nature and of man, the source 



CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 155 

and explanation alike of existence and of science. 
The Idea, which is the only appropriate and 
adequate object of absolute cognition, Hegel be- 
lieves himself to have attained, and his whole 
philosophy, as exhibited in the Encyclopcedia, is 
an attempt to trace the chief phases and forms of 
its development. In direction the development is 
from abstract to concrete, from simple to complex, 
from barest poverty to fullest wealth of content ; in 
character it is rhythmic, reasoned, dialectic; and 
the character of the movement determines its 
direction, its whole course, and ultimate goal, 
seeing that in affirming itself the thought with 
which philosophy is conversant likewise denies 
itself, yet so as thereby, instead of destroying 
itself, to reconcile itself to itself, and this through 
innumerable forms which become ever more con- 
crete and comprehensive, until the whole content 
of the Absolute Idea is evolved. Owing to the 
very nature of the Hegelian dialectic, the Hegelian 
philosophy is threefold alike as a whole and in its 
parts. It must treat of the Idea in itself, in which 
case it is Logic; or of the Idea in its other or 
external form, and then it is the Philosophy of 
Nature ; or of the Idea in its return to itself, when 
it is the Philosophy of Spirit. In like manner the 
threefold rhythm of the dialectic process causes 
Logic to resolve itself into the Science of Being, the 



156 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

Science of the Essence, and the Science of the 
Notion ; the Philosophy of Nature into Mechanics, 
Physics, and Organics ; and the Philosophy of Spirit 
into the Doctrine of Subjective Spirit, the Doctrine 
of Objective Spirit, and the Doctrine of Absolute 
Spirit, the first of which comprehends Anthro- 
pology, Phenomenology, and Psychology, while 
the second deals with Legal Right, Morality, and 
Ethical Obedience, and the third embraces the 
spheres of Art, Religion, and Absolute Philosophy. 
Thus the fundamental sciences are represented as 
having each a fixed and appropriate place, as bound 
together by ties of rational affinity, and as the 
necessary and constituent members of a vast har- 
monious and organic system of knowledge. Hegel 
must, consequently, be credited with having made 
an enormous advance on all schemes of classification 
of the sciences by mere logical division, external 
arrangement, or figurate representation. He has 
aimed at a real incorporation of the special sciences 
into a general science, at a thorough reduction of 
them under a comprehensive doctrine, at a correla- 
tion of them based on consideration of the entire 
contents of each. This may well render us averse 
to dwell on errors of detail in his views. These are 
neither few nor difficult to discover, and have been 
often indicated. Hegel has, perhaps, oftener failed 
than succeeded in defining the limits of the par- 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 157 

ticular sciences. It is only in a very general way 
that his scheme of co-ordination can be defended. 
The defects of his Philosophy of Nature are notori- 
ous, and the great merits of his Philosophy of Spirit 
are blended with serious faults. But to ignore the 
truth and grandeur of his general theory of the 
correlation and combination of the sciences in 
critically gazing at such imperfections must be 
pronounced almost as irrational and unjust as to 
doubt or deny the brightness of the sun because a 
telescopic examination shows it to be mottled over 
with a number of dark spots. Whatever be the 
faults of Hegel's Encyclopedia — although they be 
even "thick as dust in vacant chambers" — this 
glory, I think, cannot fairly be denied to it, that 
there, for the first time, appeared a system of such 
a character and scope, so vast in its range of con- 
ception, so rich in suggestion and doctrine, and so 
skilfully constructed, as to present to the mind 
something like what a Science of the Sciences 
ought to be. 

I refrain not only from urging particular objec- 
tions to the Hegelian scheme of scientific co-ordina- 
tion, but also those general objections which might 
be drawn from the nature of the Hegelian Idea, and 
of the Hegelian dialectic. These objections may be 
both relevant and conclusive, but they obviously 
raise the whole question of the truth or falsity of 



158 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCE8. 

the Hegelian philosophy, which is a question far too 
large to be here discussed. The late Prof. Harms, 
in his Geschichte der Psychologie (pp. 42-48), has 
rejected the Hegelian classification especially on 
the ground that the dialectic process is a form 
of evolution inconsistent with either the sciences 
or their objects differing otherwise than in degree, 
although the facts of experience show that they 
differ essentially and specifically. It is an objec- 
tion to which I cannot attribute much weight. 
It may be difficult to conceive that any process 
of evolution can produce certain differences, but 
it is also difficult to show that they may not, and 
off-hand appeals to experience on the question are 
to be deprecated. Then, of all forms of evolution, 
the Hegelian seems to be the one against which 
the objection must strike with the least force, 
seeing that the Hegelian dialectic, while a process 
which goes on without interruption or cessation, is 
also one of which each stage has a certain essence 
and peculiar character of its own, each of the three 
moments or acts included in it being relatively 
distinct. The evolutionism of Hegel does not 
attempt, like that of Darwin, and at least like 
that of contemporary materialism, to explain de- 
velopment entirely by gradation. It affirms un- 
broken continuity of movement, but at the same 
time maintains that the movement throughout 



CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 159 

includes distinctions of nature, not merely differ- 
ences of degree. The only objection on which I 
deem it necessary to insist is that a doctrine of 
the sciences ought to be based on, and built up 
by, a direct study of the sciences, instead of being 
drawn out of the bosom of a metaphysical philo- 
sophy. It must be reached through induction, 
not from deduction ; through analysis and general- 
isation, not by synthesis and specialisation ; by an 
upward, not a downward movement. It should be 
the product of philosophic thought, but of such 
thought in its first stage of advance on the thought 
which has produced the various sciences. It is 
one of the means with which the intellect must 
provide itself in order to apprehend ultimate and 
absolute truth. The view that a doctrine of the 
sciences must be derived from a doctrine of science, 
and even from a doctrine of Being, is very plausible, 
yet very erroneous. A doctrine of the sciences 
undoubtedly implies a doctrine of science, and even 
a doctrine of Being; but for this very reason it 
must precede them, and they can only be attained 
through it. What is first in the order of nature 
is last in the order of knowledge. To reach the 
centre of truth, every point which lies between it 
and the circumference must be passed through. 
Hegel disregarded all considerations of this kind. 
He started from what he believed to be truth 



160 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCE8. 

higher than the truths of science without having 
made use of the sciences to reach it. He began 
with philosophy at its highest, sought to work it 
all out by a uniform method from an absolute first 
point, and so to incorporate into it the sciences, 
to assign to each of them its place, and to exhibit 
their relationships. This I hold to have been a 
radically erroneous procedure. I must be content, 
however, simply to state the conviction, having 
indicated at the commencement of my previous 
paper what I deem to be the true position and 
function of a doctrine of the sciences in the organ- 
ism of philosophy. 

De Tracy. Two years before the publication of Hegel's 
jEneyclopcedia a celebrated French philosopher, 
A. L. C. Destutt de Tracy, completed a Cours 
d'Ideologie (1801-15, 5 vols.), in which he attempted 
to trace a plan of the whole edifice of science in 
accordance with the general philosophical prin- 
ciples of Locke and Condillac. He maintains that 
the foundation of all science must be acquaintance 
with the principles implied in the formation of 
science — the knowledge of how knowledge, which 
consists of ideas, is obtained from sensations or 
feelings. Ideology must be, consequently, the 
fundamental science, and it includes three depart- 
mental sciences — Ideology in the narrower sense, 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 161 

Grammar, and Logic — which treat respectively of 
the formation, the expression, and the combination 
of ideas. Then, our means of knowledge may be 
applied either to the study of what is within or 
of what is beyond our power — either to the study 
of the operations of the will or of the properties 
of nature — and hence there are other two groups 
of sciences. The sciences which refer to the will 
are Political Economy, Morals, and Jurisprudence; 
those which refer to external nature are Physics, 
Geometry, and Arithmetic. 

Such is De Tracy's scheme of classification. 
Obviously the enumeration of sciences in the 
second and third divisions is very incomplete, and 
the arrangement of them careless. The omission 
of ^Esthetics, the Science of History, and especially 
Theology, cannot fail to be remarked. And even 
the leading conception of his scheme — the view 
that the primary science must be a science of the 
conditions and processes implied in the formation 
of science — is extremely questionable. How are 
we to ascertain the conditions and processes of 
science except through a study of the sciences, 
and how shall we study them unless they exist? 
An Ideology not drawn from ideas, a Grammar not 
dependent on languages, a Logic which does not 
presuppose the reasonings and methods of science, 
must be most unworthy to be called sciences. 

L 



162 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 



IV. FROM BENTHAM TO GIOBERTI. 

Bentham. Jeremy Bentham and Samuel Taylor Coleridge 
were the Englishmen who at the period now 
reached discussed the problem of the classification 
of the sciences. The former in the fifth appendix 
to his Chrestomathia, first published in 1816, did 
so. His scheme assumes that " directly or in- 
directly, wellbeing, in some shape or other, or in 
several shapes, or all shapes taken together, is the 
subject of every thought, and object of every action, 
on the part of every known Being, who is, at the 
same time, a sensitive and thinking Being"; that 
" art and science so run along everywhere together 
that every division performed on the one may, on 
any occasion, be considered as applying to the 
other " ; that all the arts and sciences meet in, and 
proceed from, a central, common, and comprehen- 
sive art and science — Eudsemonics; and that the 
distribution of this art and science into the various 
arts and sciences ought to be exhaustive, and may 
be made so through lengthened dichotomous divi- 
sion, continued bifurcate ramification. These as- 
sumptions are not to be admitted. The first is 
the basis of utilitarianism, but denied by all who 
reject utilitarianism; the second ignores the fact 
that the points of view of science and of art are 



\ 
CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 163 

so different that every science is of use in several 
arts, and that every art presupposes several 
sciences ; the third falls with the two assump- 
tions which precede it and on which it rests; 
and the fourth has been so discredited in every 
department of inductive study that the belief in 
the applicability of dichotomous division either to 
the realities of nature or to their reflections in 
thought is now justly deemed by scientific men 
a superstition. 

The all-comprehensive art and science of Eudae- 
monics may be regarded, according to Bentham, 
specially either as art or science, and the name 
Eudaemonics may be specially appropriated to the 
former, and Ontology to the latter. " In every part 
of the common field, concomitant and correspondent 
to EudcBmonics, considered as an art, runs Ontology, 
considered as a science." Ontology is, therefore, 
the trunk of the tree of science, while the other 
sciences are branches of that tree formed by suc- 
cessive bifurcations. The tree itself is, conse- 
quently, a Ramean tree. Thus Ontology is divided 
into Coenoscopic (Metaphysics) and Idioscopic ; 
Idioscopic Ontology into Somatology and Pneu- 
matology ; Somatology into Posology and Poiology, 
and Pneumatology into Nooscopic and Pathoscopic ; 
and so on, until the result is reached that Poso- 
scopic Somatics includes Geometry, Arithmetic, and 



164 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

Algebra ; Poioscopic Somatics, Astronomy, Botany, 
Zoology, Experimental Philosophy, and Technology; 
Nooscopic Pneumatics, Logic, Grammar, and Rhet- 
oric ; and Pathoscopic Pneumatics, ^Esthetics, Exe- 
getic Ethics, Private Ethics, and the Political 
Sciences. The process by which this result is at- 
tained is not only long and wearisome, but at 
almost every stage very questionable. Theology 
is entirely ignored. Bentham, like Hobbes, sup- 
posed it not entitled to any place among the 
sciences. His whole scheme, indeed, reminds us of 
that of Hobbes. It is as self-consistent and even 
more elaborated, but shows less vigour and perspic- 
acity, and more narrowness and pedantry of mind. 
Its nomenclature is hideous, but ingenious and 
significant. In the encyclopaedic language of Ben- 
tham, Arithmetic is Gnostosymbolic, Alegomorphic, 
Pososcopic, Somatic, Coenoscopic Ontology ; Zoology 
is Embioscopic, Epigeioscopic, Physiurgic, Poso- 
scopic, Somatic, Idioscopic Ontology ; and Rhetoric 
is Pathocinetic, Ccenonesioscopic, Nooscopic, Pneu- 
matic Ontology. These are wonderful and fearful 
propositions at first sight or first hearing, but any 
reader possessed of a little Greek may easily trans- 
late them into English, and will learn something by 
doing so. 1 

1 Bentham's Chrestomathia is contained in vol. viii. of Bowling's 
edition of his works. 



CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 165 

Coleridge divided the sciences into Pure Sciences, Coleridge, 
which axe built on the relations of ideas to each 
other, and Mixed and Applied Sciences, which are 
built on the relations of ideas to the external world. 
The Pure Sciences he subdivided into Formal and 
Real, the former exhibiting the forms of thought, 
and the latter treating of Being itself, of the true 
nature and existence of the external universe, of 
the guiding principles within us, and of the Great 
Cause of all. Grammar, Logic, and Mathematics 
he classed as the Formal Sciences; Metaphysics, 
Morals, and Theology as the Real Sciences ; Mech- 
anics, Hydrostatics, Pneumatics, Optics, and As- 
tronomy as the Mixed Sciences; and the various 
branches of Experimental Philosophy, the theories 
of the Fine Arts and of the Useful Arts, and 
Natural History, with its applications to Medicine 
and Surgery, as the Applied Sciences. 

It is not difficult to discover grave defects in this 
classification. The Real Sciences cannot be Pure 
Sciences if Coleridge's own definitions of Real 
Sciences and Pure Sciences be correct. The Mixed 
and Applied Sciences, if only mixed and applied, 
have no right to be classed as co-ordinate with the 
Pure Sciences; and if in any degree distinct and 
independent sciences, they must be to the same 
extent either Formal or Real Sciences. Most of 
them are obviously entitled to be ranked among 



166 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

the so-called Real Sciences. Within the several 
groups the order in which the particular sciences 
follow one another is not the most natural order. 
For all defects of this kind Coleridge himself may 
not be responsible, as he complained that under 
editorial revision his work was (to use his own 
words) "so bedeviled that I am ashamed to own 
it." 1 

Janneiii. Cataldo Jannelli, a clear-headed Italian author, 
while endeavouring to correct and develop in his 
Cenni Bulla natura e necessity delle cosse e delle 
storie umane (1817) the doctrine of Vico, dealt, 
although only to a slight extent, with the problem 
of the classification of the sciences. While recog- 
nising the value of the work achieved by Vico in 
the Principii di Scienza Nuova, and his right to 
be regarded as the founder of the philosophy of 
history and the improver of all sciences dependent 
on that philosophy, he was sufficiently independent 
to criticise even the central doctrine and most com- 
prehensive generalisation in the great Neapolitan's 
system of thought. For Vico's divine, heroic, and 
human ages he substituted three ages partly corre- 
spondent to and partly corrective of them — namely, 

1 As to Coleridge's classification see the third section of his Treatise 
on Method, prefatory to the Encyclopaedia Metropolitana, which 
began to appear in 1817. 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 167 

the ages of sense, imagination, and reason — and 
thus with a considerable measure of success im- 
proved on his predecessor's description of the stages 
of human development and distribution of the kinds 
of knowledge, without rejection of the great idea of 
a natural law of the development of life in the 
history alike of the human race and the human 
individual His criticism left psychology, sociology, 
and evolutionism none the less indebted to Vico, 
while it led him to recognise as of supreme import- 
ance the claims of two other sciences — namely, 
teleologia (the science of final causes) and ideologia 
(the science of first causes). His general dis- 
tribution of the sciences is into intuitive or 
theoretical and operative or practical sciences, — 
a much too simple classification. 

G. D. Romagnosi (1761-1835), a very eminent Romag- 
Italian jurist and publicist, and a wise and inde- 
pendent citizen in a very difficult and critical 
period of his country's history, gave expression in 
one of his many writings to what may well be 
regarded as an extravagant view of the importance 
of an encyclopaedic distribution of the sciences. I 
quote his words below. 1 So far as I am aware, he 

1 Vedute fondamentale sxdV Arte Logica, Lib. i. Sez. i., § 18 : " Un 
albero enciclopedico delle scienze ben fatto forma V ultima e la piu 
grande espressione del logico magistero." 



nosL 



168 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

himself made no attempt to supply the sort of 
classification he so highly appreciated. 
Longo. It seems certain, however, from the Appendix to 

the second volume of Prof. Vincenzo di Giovanni's 
Storia della FUosofia in Sicilia, — a very inter- 
esting and every way admirable work, — that the 
problem must have been long and earnestly dealt 
with by a Sicilian scientist, the Cav. Agatino 
Longo. Greatly to my regret I have not been 
able to obtain his writings on the subject — one 
which must have occupied his mind more or less 
for over thirty years. Unfortunately for my pur- 
pose Di Giovanni has given no information as to 
their contents beyond what is implied in their 
titles, and as they have all been published in Sicily, 
and for the most part in Sicilian periodicals, gener- 
ally short-lived and of very limited circulation, I 
have not been able to obtain them, and must there- 
fore content myself with reproducing a few of the 
titles given by Giovanni in the work already 
mentioned, viz. :— 

Longo, Cav. A. — 

Prolusioni accademiche, lette nell* universiti di 
Catania. (La prima di esse ivi stampata nei 
1820 presenta una nuova classificazione delle 
scienze : la seconda inserita nel t. xiii. del. Gior. 
di scienze lettre ed arti offre partizioni della 
erudizione e delle arti. 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 169 

Sul bisogno d' una nuova classificazione delle cog- 
nizioni, Cat. 1827, e nel tomo xxii. del Giorn. di 
scienze lettre ed arti per la Sicilia. 

Atlante universalle delle cognizioni, o Tavole sinottiche 
contenenti la classificazione sistematica delle 
scienze secondo il metodo naturale. (Di questa 
grand opera ne dk V annunzio nel t. xxxiv. di 
detto Giornale, e nel xiii dell' Efemeridi sicole.) 

Osservazioni sulla Geneografia dello scibile del sign. 
Pamphilis: nel t. xxxv. 

Sul valore del vocabolo Filosofia, ed enumerazione delle 
scienze che vi s' includono. Cat. 1850. 

Delle partizioni della filosofia generate, e dei metodi 
di classificazione. Cat. 1850. 



Father Giovachino Ventura set forth his views on Ventura, 
the classification of the sciences in his De Methodo 
Philosophandi, published at Rome in 1828. But 
his traditionalism, his subjection of reason to au- 
thority and of science to faith, his want of secular 
knowledge and exclusively theological habits of 
thought, rendered it impossible for him to discuss 
the theme with much success. He assigned to the 
encyclopaedic tree of knowledge three branches — 
one bearing the sciences of authority, another the 
sciences of ratiocination, and the third the sciences 
of observation. These he represented as coincident 
with the Ethics, Logic, and Physics of ancient 
philosophy. That view, it need scarcely be said, is 
utterly erroneous. It is, however, not more so than 



170 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

this other, closely connected with it, that the object 
of Ethics, thus understood, is God ; of Logic, Man ; 
and of Physics, Body. Ethics is divided into 
Metaphysics and Jurisprudence ; Logic into Ideology 
and Logic strictly so called; and Physics into 
General and Special Physics. The process of sub- 
division is pushed to a great length. 1 The self- 
confidence of the renowned Theatine orator was 
undimmed by any suspicion of ignorance, and so he 
mapped out the universe of knowledge with magis- 
terial minuteness. It would serve no good purpose 
to follow him in details, which are without interest 
in themselves, and which belong to a scheme false 
in its principles and misleading in its main lines. 

Ferrarese. L. Ferrarese published, in 1828, a Saggio di una 
nuova classificazione delle scienze. It contains good 
remarks on the importance of a right distribution 
of the system of knowledge, but the classification 
which it sets forth is not based on sound principles, 
and by no means satisfies the necessary requirements. 
According to Ferrarese, the Science of Man must be 
the foundation of all the sciences ; but he has for- 
gotten to attempt to prove that there can be a 
Science of Man without a foundation supplied by 
other and simpler sciences. He classifies the sciences 
exclusively according to the modes of their helpful- 

1 Op. cil, art vii., pp. 241-300. 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 171 

ness to man, on the ground that they will not 
otherwise be so useful to him as they might be ; 
but in so doing he overlooks that even if this 
allegation were correct — which it is not — it would 
be altogether insufficient to establish that the 
sciences should have their place and rank deter- 
mined, not by intrinsic, but by extrinsic considera- 
tions; not by the nature of the truths of which 
they consist, but by the uses to which they may 
be put. To the tree of science he assigns three 
great branches, because the sciences contribute, in 
his opinion, to one or other of three great ends 
— the maintenance of man in health or sound- 
ness (salute) of body or mind, the furtherance of 
his perfection, and the prevention of his degradation 
— although these ends are obviously so closely as- 
sociated that any one of them can only be realised 
in the measure that the others are promoted, and 
that, consequently, to distribute the sciences by them 
into distinct groups must be futile. The fundamental 
science Ferrarese calls Anthropography, and he de- 
scribes it as dividing into Descriptive and Compara- 
tive Anthropography. To these two branches the 
mathematical, physical, natural, and medical sciences 
are represented as belonging. The third branch 
begins with Telestics, the general science of the 
perfection of man, alike as regards his bodily, in- 
tellectual, and moral faculties. It is supposed to 



172 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

support Paedagogy, the philosophical, juridical, and 
moral sciences, history, and literature. 

De Pam- The treatise of Giacinto de Pamphilis — Geneografia 
p dello Scibile — was published a year later than that 

of Ferrarese, 1 and is even more ingenious. It places 
the centre of the sciences not in man alone, as the 
work of Ferrarese does, but both in nature and 
man, since the former is the objective cause, and the 
latter the subjective cause, and these causes act 
incessantly on each other. It refers the origin of 
knowledge to "the reciprocal circular influence" 
between nature and man, and makes this fact the 
principle of the division of the sciences. Hence it 
distributes the sciences into three orders: 1. Ob- 
jective Sciences, those of the Not-Me ; 2. Subjective 
Sciences, those of the Me; and, 3. Objective-sub- 
jective and Subjective-objective Sciences, those of 
the Me in relation to the Not-Me, and of the Not- 
Me in relation to the Me ; or, in other words, into 
Physical, Metaphysical, and Moral Sciences. These 
orders are brought into connection in a somewhat in- 
tricate and arbitrary manner, so as to yield such 
groups as Grammar, Logic, and Morals ; Cosmology, 
Psychology, and Theology ; Philoagathy, Philocaly, 
and Philosophy ; Metaphysics, Ontology, and Ideo- 
logy ; all the members of which deal directly with 

1 A second edition appeared in 1869. 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 173 

the phenomenal, yet imply the transcendental and 
absolute. It would occupy too much of the space at 
my disposal to explain and criticise the processes by 
which these groups are formed. Any reader whose 
curiosity regarding the scheme is unsatisfied may be 
referred not only to the work in which it was pro- 
pounded, but also to the examination of it by Prof. 
Longo, Osservazioni sulla Geneografia dello scibile 
del sig. Pamphilis. 1 

Dr Neil Arnott, in the introduction to his Elements n«i 
of Physics, — a popular work, of which the first edi- 
tion appeared in 1828, — divided the whole sum of 
man's knowledge of nature into Natural History and 
Science or Philosophy. The former treats of the 
materials of the universe — e.g., minerals, vegetables, 
animals ; or, in other words, describes the kingdoms 
of nature. The latter treats of the manners or kinds 
of motion or change ; or, in other words, exhibits 
the general truths or laws of nature. It ought, in 
Dr Arnott's opinion, to be distributed into four dis- 
tinct sciences — Physics, Chemistry, the Science of 
Life, and the Science of Mind — because all pheno- 
mena are referable to four distinct classes, — the 
physical, chemical, vital, and mental. These four 
sciences " may be said to form the pyramid of 
Science, of which Physics is the base, while the 

1 Giorn. di scienze lettere ed arti per la SicUia, t xxxv. 



174 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

others constitute succeeding layers in the order 
mentioned, the whole having certain mutual re- 
lations and dependencies well-figured by the parts 
of a pyramid." Mathematics " may be considered 
as a subsidiary department of human science, 
created by the mind itself, to facilitate the study 
of the others." Theology is included in the Science 
of Mind. It was thus that Arnott enunciated 
an idea of a hierarchy of fundamental sciences 
closely resembling that of Comte, and, indeed, 
superior to it in the two points in which it differs 
from it — namely, in neither representing Astron- 
omy as a fundamental science, nor the Science of 
Mind as merely a department of the Science of 
Life. There is no evidence, so far as I am aware, 
that his anticipation of Comte was due to any 
acquaintance with the writings of Saint - Simon. 
He enunciated, however, Saint - Simon's general 
idea, although only in a very general way. He 
made no attempt to build on it, as Comte did, 
a universal philosophy, a science of the sciences. 
How incompetent he was to perform such an achieve- 
ment, had he been ambitious enough to undertake 
it, we may judge from the feeble book he published 
in 1861, entitled A Survey of Human Progress. 
Yet in this work he developed in some degree the 
conception just indicated as contained in his earlier 
one. He, as Dr Bain says, "brought out more 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 175 

decisively the distinction between Sciences and Arts, 
and between the Concrete and the Abstract Depart- 
ments of Science." Still distributing that know- 
ledge of phenomena to which he restricted the term 
Science or Philosophy into the' four fundamental 
Sciences of Physics, Chemistry, Physiology, and 
Psychology, he represented the knowledge of things 
or objects called Natural History and the devices or 
practical applications of knowledge called Art as 
similarly divisible, so that the departments of 
Natural History, of Science, and of Art form three 
parallel and co-ordinate series, Astronomy and Geo- 
graphy corresponding to Physics, Mineralogy and 
Geology to Chemistry, Botany and Zoology to Physi- 
ology, and the History of Man to Psychology, while 
the Arts must be classified as Mechanical, Chemical, 
Physiological, and Mental. 

We now reach Auguste Comte, than whom, Comte. 
perhaps, no one has done more for philosophy as 
positive. He owes the high place he holds among 
philosophers to the power and skill and general 
truthfulness of his elaboration of the doctrine of the 
so-called positive sciences as a whole, not to the 
merits of his treatment of the particular problem 
of the classification of the sciences. He claimed, 
but had no right whatever to claim, that he 
originated the classification which he adopted. If 



176 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

that classification possess any merits, they must 
be ascribed to Dr Burdin, who conceived it, and to 
Saint-Simon, who first received and published it; 
not to Comte, although he showed how much could 
be made of it. As it is with Comte's name, how- 
ever, that the classification is almost universally 
associated, it is in connection with him, and as ex- 
pounded in his Cours de Philosophie Positive (1830- 
42), that I shall briefly consider and criticise it. 

The classification cannot be dissevered from the 
celebrated so-called " law of the three states." That 
alleged law, as it is understood and expounded by 
Comte, means that the human mind in every de- 
partment of thought and inquiry reaches such rela- 
tive truth as it can attain, and so enters into the 
state called positive, or, in other words, arrives at 
science only by passing through a theological and 
metaphysical state, both essentially false and con- 
jectural, although both containing some measure of 
truth and pervaded by a certain nisus toward the 
certainty of science. Thus apprehended, the law 
necessarily implies that there can be no true the- 
ology or true metaphysics, and that whatever 
professes to be theological or metaphysical science 
must be discarded as pretentious delusion. Comte 
cannot be charged in this respect with want of 
consistency ; he refused to assign either to theology 
or metaphysics any place among the sciences. That 



CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 177 

in doing so he most seriously erred I shall not here 
endeavour to show, as I have elsewhere examined 
his views on this point at considerable length. 1 

Comte further defined and limited the field of 
his investigation by excluding from consideration 
merely composite and derivative sciences. He 
distributed the sciences into two classes — Abstract 
Sciences conversant with general laws, and Con- 
crete Sciences conversant with the explanation of 
particular existing things by means of general 
laws ; and held the former only to be fundamental, 
and alone to require from the philosopher classifi- 
cation. He thus greatly simplified his task. There 
can be no doubt that the distinction on which he 
rested the simplification is a very valuable one. 
It is now almost universally accepted. 

The Abstract Sciences, Comte held, must fall into 
a single linear series, each member of which has 
its place determined by its relative simplicity, 
generality, and independence. This does not pre- 
vent them from being divisible into Mathematical 
and Physical, or the Physical Sciences from being 
divisible into Inorganic Physics (comprehending 
Astronomy and Physics proper) and Organic Physics 

1 Philosophy of History, pp. 267-278. Iu ch. x. of my Historical 
Philosophy in France I have treated somewhat folly of the natural- 
ism and positivism in the doctrine of Comte, bat not at all of his 
attempted classification of the sciences. 

M 



178 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

(containing Biology and Sociology) ; but it implies 
that Mathematical Science must precede Physical 
Science, and that the five fundamentally distinct 
Physical Sciences must have been evolved in the 
following order: Astronomy, Physics, Chemistry, 
Biology, and Sociology. A relatively simple, 
abstract, and independent science must always 
precede one which is more special, complex, and 
dependent. 

These views of Comte raise various questions. 
One is this : Is there, even of sciences of the kind 
which he calls positive, only one series? Is there 
not, for example, a Psychical as well as Physical 
series of such sciences ? The material and the 
mental spheres of existence are conspicuously 
different and appear to be essentially distinct. 
The facts on which the physical sciences are built 
are all observed externally by the senses, while 
those on which mental science is built must be 
apprehended by internal consciousness; we cannot 
observe a single fact of physical nature by intro- 
spection, nor a single fact of mind by perception. 
From this it seems to follow that, although Psy- 
chology may possibly be the root of a series of 
sciences parallel to the Physical Sciences, neither 
itself nor any science springing from it — as, for 
example, Sociology — can be included in a series of 
Physical Sciences. And certainly Comte has not 



CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 179 

shown this conclusion to be unwarranted. The 
views he maintained as to the position, character, 
and method of the Science of Mind cannot com- 
mend themselves to any competent student. The 
arguments from which he inferred that Psychology 
is merely a department of Physiology, and may 
even be identified with Phrenology, are singularly 
weak and irrelevant, and have often been adequately 
exposed. 

There is a still more penetrating question: Is 
there a fixed line or series either of the physical 
or psychical sciences? Is there in any group of 
the sciences a straight line of succession and neces- 
sary order of filiation? Comte maintained that 
there is, while Herbert Spencer, in an essay on 
"The Genesis of Science," has argued, with great 
ingenuity and vigour, that there is not ; that " the 
conception of a serial arrangement of the sciences 
is a vicious one " ; that " there is no ' one rational 
order among a host of possible systems'"; that 
" there is no • true filiation of the sciences/ " That 
Comte's doctrine is very inadequate and inaccurate 
Spencer seems to me to have conclusively shown. 
Indeed, a very general inspection of the procedure 
of the mind in the formation of the sciences must 
suffice to convince us that Comte has erred in his 
views as to the filiation of the sciences. The 
nature of the connection, or so-called filiation of 



180 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

the sciences, must depend on the nature of their 
formation or genesis. The former must be simple 
or complex according as the latter is simple or 
complex. Now Comte supposed the latter to be 
simple, while in the positive sciences, both physical 
and psychical, it is really and obviously complex. 
It is not a single, but a twofold process. In the 
formation of any of the positive sciences, since a 
positive science is the explanation of facts by laws, 
the mind for some time predominantly and always 
to some extent follows an ascending direction, rising 
from facts to laws, from sense to science. On this 
path its instruments are induction and its auxiliary 
processes, and with their aid it evolves laws of 
ever-increasing comprehensiveness and simplicity. 
But the reverse method, the descending order, must 
likewise be followed. The results of induction 
become the premisses of deduction. The laws in- 
ductively reached yield deductive solutions of 
problems previously inexplicable. But since the 
progress of science thus depends not on one pro- 
cess of discovery, but on two processes, the one 
the inverse of the other, the order of the evolution 
of the sciences must manifestly be very different 
from what it would be if determined by a single 
process, whether induction or deduction. If the 
formation of science were an exclusively induc- 
tive process, the law of the development of the 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 181 

sciences would be one of continuous movement 
from complexity and particularity to simplicity 
and generality; if exclusively deductive, the re- 
sultant law would be just the opposite, and precisely 
what Comte supposed it to be, one of uninterrupted 
advance from the general to the special, from the 
simple to the complex, from the abstract to the 
concrete; but the process of scientific discovery 
being both inductive and deductive, the order of 
the evolution of the sciences cannot be entirely or 
continuously in either of the directions indicated, 
and cannot be either so absolute in itself or so 
easily ascertainable by us as Comte would have us 
to believe. In laying down his law of the filiation 
of the sciences he overlooked all that is empirical 
and inductive in the sciences, treated each science 
as if it had been a single truth, and assumed that 
the order of the succession of the sciences was de- 
termined solely by pure deductive reason. In all 
this he erred most grievously, and simplified his 
problem most unduly. If science can be built up 
only by the combined resources alike of induction 
and deduction, we may be entitled to say, in a 
general way, that this science must precede that, 
but not to say, in an absolute way, that this whole 
science must precede that whole science. 

Are we to conclude, then, that Spencer is wholly 
right and Comte wholly wrong? That is by no 



182 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

means necessary. The association of induction and 
deduction, of generalisation and specialisation, of 
analysis and synthesis, in the growth of science, 
requires us to believe that the sciences spring up 
together and influence each other to an extent 
unrecognised by Comte, but not to disbelieve that 
some sciences are naturally antecedent to others, 
or even that the sciences of which the phenomena 
are most general and simple must be further de- 
veloped than those conversant with phenomena 
more special and complex. Biology may not only 
develop simultaneously with Physics and Chemis- 
try, but even suggest to them problems on the 
solution of which their progress is greatly de- 
pendent, while yet all its doctrines must be super- 
ficial unless based on the teachings of a Physics 
and a Chemistry which have attained a relatively 
high perfection. Although Comte did not see 
with sufficient clearness to what extent the sciences 
develop spontaneously and simultaneously, he was 
not mistaken in so far as he held that* one fun- 
damental science does come before another — on 
the whole, although not wholly — and that in 
virtue of the relative simplicity, generality, and 
independence of the laws which they set forth. 
We may assign full weight to all that is true in 
the objections urged by Spencer in his criticism of 
Comte's scheme of filiation of the sciences, and yet 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 183 

reasonably hold that, in the main, it is Comte who 
is in the right, and that Spencer's view that there is 
no true order of filiation of the sciences is an ex- 
aggerated inference from his facts, and implies that 
the progress of knowledge is without method or law. 
Let us now confine our attention for a moment 
to the fundamental physical sciences of Comte — 
Astronomy, Physics, Chemistry, and Physiology. 
It is obvious, I think, that the first — Astronomy — 
is not of the same rank as the others. It is not 
a science of general properties, but of particular 
objects, which is what no fundamental science is. 
The fundamental sciences are not classed accord- 
ing to individual objects. Every object is com- 
plex, and can only be fully explained by the 
concurrent application of various sciences. The 
stars have a mathematics, physics, and chemistry; 
a mineralogy also, and perhaps a botany and 
zoology, and conceivably a psychology and soci- 
ology. What Comte means by Astronomy is, of 
course, only the mathematics and physics of the 
stars; but why, then, make it co-ordinate with 
the mathematics and physics which include it, 
or by their synthesis constitute it? The mathe- 
matics and physics of the stars would require to be 
entirely distinct from the mathematics and physics 
of the earth — i.e., to be no mathematics and physics 
at all, but things essentially different, before they 



184 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

can be entitled to the place which Comte assigns 
them — a place separate from all other mathe- 
matics and physics. Even if it were true that 
Astronomy became positive science long before 
terrestrial physics, this would prove no more than 
that it was the simplest and most manageable part 
of physics ; it would in nowise prove that it was 
no part of physics. But the alleged fact cannot be 
made out. For just as it was impossible to under- 
stand the geometrical relations of the celestial 
bodies while ignorant of the geometrical relations 
of terrestrial bodies, so it was impossible to apply 
physical conceptions and generalisations to the stars 
without having drawn them from our experience of 
the earth, or at least without applying them at the 
same time to the earth. The laws of motion, weight, 
force, &c., which rule in celestial, rule also in ter- 
restrial physics. The great law of gravitation, 
which regulates the motion of the stars, was, 
according to the well-known story, suggested to 
Newton by the fall of an apple, and could certainly 
not have been ascertained and verified by him if he 
had been ignorant of the laws of falling bodies, the 
law of the composition of forces, and the law of 
centrifugal force, which Galileo and Huygens had 
previously discovered to rule terrestrial phenomena. 
We must, therefore, strike out Astronomy from the 
list of fundamental physical sciences. There then 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 185 

remain only Physics, Chemistry, and Biology. Are 
these fundamental physical sciences ? Are they the 
only fundamental physical sciences ? So far as our 
present knowledge goes, we must, I believe, answer 
both questions in the affirmative. These sciences 
are fundamental, not being able to be resolved into 
any other sciences or into one another. They are 
the only fundamental physical sciences because the 
only irresolvable attributes of matter are physical 
forces, chemical affinities, and vital properties. Those 
who make a longer list overlook a distinction without 
which the whole subject of the relationship of the 
sciences must be an inextricable imbroglio — the dis- 
tinction between fundamental and derivative, prim- 
ary and secondary, simple and complex sciences. 

Another French philosopher, contemporaneously Ampfee. 
with but quite independently of Comte, strenuously 
occupied his mind during many years on the classi- 
fication of the sciences, and published, in 1834, the 
first part of an Essai sur la Philosophic des Sciences, 
the second part of which, completing the work, only 
appeared in 1843. This philosopher was the illus- 
trious Andr^-Marie Ampere, a man equally remark- 
able for the extent and the profundity of his 
knowledge, keenly interested in all the sciences, a 
brilliant discoverer in several of them, and in par- 
ticular, as a thoroughly competent authority, the 



186 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

late Principal Forbes, of St Andrews, observed, " at 
least as well entitled as any other philosopher who 
has yet appeared to be called 'the Newton of 
Electricity.'" 

M. Ampere proposes his classification as founded 
upon a consideration of the sciences themselves. It 
is, he conceives, in accordance with the conditions 
of natural classification as exhibited, for example, 
in Botany. It aims to bring together analogous 
sciences, and to group them according to their real 
affinities. It is certainly remarkable for its regu- 
larity and symmetry. It proceeds thus : All science 
has reference to one of two general objects — the 
material world and thought. This gives rise to the 
natural division of the sciences into sciences of 
matter and of thought, or, as Ampere calls them, 
cosmological and noological sciences. Hence all our 
knowledge is embraced under one or other of two 
kingdoms. Each kingdom is in its turn the subject 
of a twofold division. The cosmological sciences 
separate into those which have for object the in- 
animate world, and those which occupy themselves 
with the world of life and organisation, the first of 
these classes comprehending the mathematical and 
the physical sciences, and the second the sciences 
relative to natural history and the medical sciences. 
In like manner, the sciences of thought divide into 
two sub-kingdoms, of which the one includes the 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 187 

noological sciences properly so called, and the other 
the social sciences. From these spring, in conse- 
quence of another division, four branches, as in the 
case of the cosmological sciences. 

We need not exhibit farther the general scheme. 
If we confine our attention to the strictly noological 
branch we shall find that it separates into two — 
the philosophical and the moral sciences. And if 
we confine ourselves to the moral sciences, we find 
these also to be two — Ethics and Thelesiology. 
Then, Ethics, which embraces all that can be known 
relative to the characters, manners, and moral con- 
duct of man, divides into two parts — Elementary 
Ethics, which includes Ethography and Physiog- 
nomony — and Ethognosy, which comprises Practical 
Morality and Ethogeny. Thus in Ethics, a science 
of the first order, there are, according to Ampfere, 
two sciences of the second order and four sciences 
of the third order. 

In the same way Thelesiology, which is con- 
versant with the will, with duty, and the end 
of man, embraces two sciences of the second order 
— Elementary Thelesiology and Thelesiognosy — 
and four of the third order — Thelesiography, 
Diceology, Apodictic Morality, and Anthropotelic. 
Thus Moral Science comprehends two sciences of 
the first order, four of the second order, and eight 
of the third order. There can be no doubt that this 



188 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

is ingenious, and it is but a very small specimen of 
the ingenuity of the scheme as a whole. Every 
science of the first class includes, according to 
Ampere, four sciences of the third order, and this 
alleged fact he explains by an alleged law of scien- 
tific thought. Intelligence in examining any sub- 
ject whatever must, he holds, follow a process of 
four stages. In the first stage, called autoptic, 
it is limited to the simple inspection of its objects ; 
in the second, the cryptoristic stage, it investigates 
their inner and hidden natures; in the third, or 
troponomic stage, it traces the changes which they 
undergo in time and place, and seeks, from the 
experience of these changes, to ascertain their laws 
of change ; and in the fourth, or cryptologic stage, 
it occupies itself with what is most uncertain, ab- 
struse, and difficult to discover in their causality 
and destination. These stages consequently corre- 
spond to four epochs of intellectual growth in indi- 
vidual and social development. 

The very regularity of the foregoing scheme is an 
objection to it. Nature is less symmetrical than it 
represents her to be. She observes order, indeed, 
and obeys mathematical laws ; but she does not in- 
cessantly go on dividing by two. She is free and 
varied in her operations, and none of her secrets of 
much value will be discovered by so simple a pro- 
cess as a succession of divisions by two. Further 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 189 

division is, in Ampere's scheme, pushed to an excess 
which tends to defeat the great end of a classifica- 
tion of the sciences. That end is so to group and 
co-ordinate the sciences that they may be seen to- 
gether as harmonious parts of a great whole in which 
the universe is truthfully mirrored. But if we pro- 
ceed to divide and divide, unsatisfied, as Wordsworth 
says, " while littleness may yet become more little," 
we break down all grandeur, destroy all life, and 
amid the multiplicity of details lose sight of those 
fundamental laws and relations which are most 
worthy of our study. If Ampere had divided less 
he would certainly have succeeded much better in 
his attempt to form a philosophy of the sciences. 
The elaborateness of his scheme weighed him down 
and prevented his rising to a general doctrine ex- 
hibiting the unity of science and reflecting the unity 
of the universe. He found that even in two volumes 
he could do no more than give a general idea of each 
of the multitude of sciences to which he assigned 
a place, although aware that an exposition of the 
fundamental truths and general methods of science 
is essential in a philosophy of the sciences. If the 
trees did not hide from himself the forest, they cer- 
tainly prevented him from describing it to others. 

The scheme under consideration has, however, 
even greater defects than those just indicated. One 
is that it makes no distinction between arts and 



190 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES, 



sciences, but treats the former as of the same nature 
and as to be placed on the same level and ranked in 
the same line with the latter. It represents, for 
example, Technology as following Chemistry and 
preceding Natural History, and often thus puts arts 
and sciences side by side- This ignoring of the true 
relationship of science and art — this confounding of 
knowledge and its application, of the quid and quid 
hwri — renders a true classification of the sciences 
absolutely impossible. And it involves another 
error as great as itself — the ignoring of the distinc- 
tion between fundamental and derivative sciences. 
Unless the arts are separated from the sciences the 
sciences themselves cannot be distributed into funda- 
mental and derivative. To set aside the distinction 
between dependent and independent at one point 
of the scheme is to necessitate its being set aside 
throughout. 

It would not be difficult to show that Ampere's 
sciences of the third order are seldom natural divi- 
sions of his sciences of the first order. In fact, the 
very conception of there being in each science of the 
first order four sciences of the third order corre- 
sponding to four distinct points of view from which 
their common subject may be studied is illusive. 
Even conceding the four points of view, it cannot be 
reasonably held that there are separate sciences to 
correspond to them. The points of view represent 









CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 191 

only stages of the scientific process ; they are only 
the series of steps by which science is attained. 
Science corresponds to the process as a whole, not to 
any particular point or stage of it. Science may 
well begin with the simple inspection of objects, and 
must, of course, end with their full comprehension ; 
but this is not the slightest reason for supposing, 
as Amp&re does, that there are sciences of simple 
inspection and sciences of full comprehension — 
autoptic sciences and cryptologic sciences. With 
all his knowledge and ingenuity Ampfere failed to 
classify the sciences aright, and still more to found a 
philosophy of the sciences. His work, however, is 
most instructive, and not unworthy even of his 
great reputation. 

The celebrated socialist, P. J. Proudhon, published Proudhon. 
in 1843 a work entitled De la Creation de VOrdre 
dans FHumanitS, in which traces of the influence 
both of Comte and Ampere are deeply marked. 
Comte's law of three states is unqualifiedly adopted 
in substance, although the terms in which it is 
expressed are changed, metaphysic being called 
philosophy or sophistic, and the doctrine of the 
sciences or positive philosophy being designated 
metaphysic, so that in Proudhon's phraseology 
the Comtist law runs thus : " Religion, philosophy, 
science ; faith, sophistic, and method (metaphysic) 



192 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

— such are the three moments of knowledge, the 
three epochs of the education of the human race." 
Ampere's classification of the sciences is expounded 
and highly commended. At the same time, it is 
held not to be the absolute or only true classification 
of them. " The mind," says Proudhon, " may find 
in Nature a multitude of systems, according to the 
point of view which it takes up, although Nature 
herself follows none of them exclusively. " He under- 
takes, in particular, to show that for the quaternary 
distribution of Ampere a ternary may be substituted, 
not less natural, regular, and precise. Of this ternary 
classification he would make the ordinary distribu- 
tion into kingdoms in Natural History — mineral, 
vegetable, and animal — the basis, and then would 
divide the sciences, according as they are descriptive 
or declarative of phenomena, or as they study forces, 
motions, progress, changes, or as they formulate laws 
and determine relations. In other words, he would 
reduce Ampere's four points or stages of the scientific 
process to three, but retain his vicious principle of 
regarding such mere points or stages as the roots 
of distinct sciences. He has not exhibited his 
ternary classification in detail, but he professes to 
have worked through the whole scheme of Ampere, 
changing it everywhere from quaternary to ternary 
— " absolutely as if I had transcribed our decimal 
arithmetic into a duodecimal arithmetic." This I 



PROM BENTHAM TO GIOBERTI. 193 

can readily believe, although I would infer from it 
not, as Proudhon does, that both systems are alike 
natural, but that both are alike arbitrary. ^^^ 

J. Duval- Jouve in his Traitide Logique> ou Essai Duval. 
sur la Thforie de la Science, 1844, has dealt with 
the classification of the sciences in pp. 374-393. He 
distributes them into cosmological and noological 
sciences, and subdivides the former into mathe- 
matical and physical classes. That is manifestly 
insufficient. The work, however, can be safely com- 
mended for its judicious counsels as to the study 
of the sciences of reasoning and of physical and 
psychological observation. 

Two Italian philosophers of rare genius, and whose RownfoL 
influence on the thought and life of their nation was 
great and salutary, — Antonio Rosmini and Vincenzo 
Gioberti, — now claim our attention ; but, of course, 
only in so far as they have dealt with the special 
problem which at present concerns us. Neither 
dealt with it as an independent problem, only to 
be solved by a comparative study of the sciences 
themselves; on the contrary, both professedly 
evolved their classification of the sciences from the 
fundamental principle of their philosophies. That 
seems to me an altogether illegitimate procedure, 
resting on an assumption as to the relation of phil- 

N 



194 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

osophy to the sciences just the reverse of the 
truth. 

Rosmini's views on the classification of the 
sciences are to be found in his New Essay on the 
Origin of Ideas (first edition, 1830), Philosophical 
System (first edition, 1845), and Logic (first edition, 
1854), the first two of which have appeared in Eng- 
lish. On the ground that every cognition must 
have matter and form, he represented the sciences 
as primarily divisible into material and formal; 
and on the ground that the form of cognition is 
at once the source of all intelligence and alone 
knowable per se, he held that the science of the 
form must precede all other sciences and supply 
the principle of their encyclopaedic arrangement. 
This first science, which he called Ideology, he re- 
garded as the only pure science, all other sciences 
being in relation to it only applied sciences. But 
he was not content merely with this division, and 
so proposed another corresponding to the aspects of 
Being, that one necessary and objective form of 
intelligence to which he believed all the other forms 
of cognition could be reduced, and also to the 
modes of mental activity by which these aspects 
of Being are apprehended. Thus, viewing Being as 
ideal, real, and moral, and intelligence as possessed 
of intuition, perception, and reason, he classified 
the sciences in the following threefold manner: 



FROM BBNTHAM TO GIOBERTI. 195 

1. Sciences of intuition, which treat of the ideal 
and include Ideology and Logic; 2. Sciences of 
perception, which treat of the real and comprehend 
Psychology and Cosmology; and, 3. Sciences of 
reasoning, which treat of what is only discoverable 
through inference and may be subdivided into 
Ontological and Deontological Sciences. The Math- 
ematical Sciences have no place in the scheme, nor 
even the Physical Sciences, the Kosminian Cosmo- 
logy being only a department of Metaphysics. The 
Ontological Sciences are said to be Ontology, 
properly so called, and Natural Theology. The 
Deontological Sciences are those which treat of the 
perfection of being, and of the way in which this 
perfection may be acquired and lost; and as they 
are distributed in a somewhat minute and decidedly 
artificial manner, it may suffice to say that they 
comprehend not only Moral sciences usually so 
called, but ^Esthetic sciences, Political sciences, 
Pedagogics, and Economy. Language and history 
are not represented as the special objects of distinct 
sciences, but a scientific study of history is recog- 
nised to be an important means of advancing the 
Philosophy of Politics. 

To Gioberti the first principle of Bosmini seemed QiobertL 
a vain abstraction and his method essentially false ; 
and he resolved for his own part to start not with 



196 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

indeterminate ideal being, but with an object at 
once ideal and real, and to evolve what it implied, 
not by a psychological method, which can only 
reflect the mind's attention to itself, but by the 
only true philosophical method, the ontological, 
which reflects the nature and manifestation of the 
object. He deemed that he found at once a point 
of departure and a law of procedure satisfying the 
requirements of the case in a synthetic judgment, 
comprehensive of all being and knowledge, for 
which the appropriate expression is the ideal for- 
mula Ens creat existentias — Being creates exist- 
ences. In his Introduzione alle studio della Filosofia 
(vol. iii. cap. v.), published in 1840, he has ex- 
plained how the sciences may be arranged in accord- 
ance with his formula. It is by a method which, if 
not eminently satisfactory, is at least eminently 
easy. The ideal formula is itself the "suprema 
formula enciclopedica" and all sciences, it is held, 
may be directly referred to one or other of its 
terms. The subject (Being) is the theme of Philo- 
sophy Proper, which includes the sciences of Onto- 
logy and Theology. The copula (Creates) yields 
the sciences which are concerned with the relation- 
ship of Being to Existences and of Existences to 
Being, the relationship of Being to Existences being 
treated of by the Science of time and space (Mathe- 
matics), and the relationship of Existences to Being 



PROM WHEWELL TO ZELLER. 197 

by the Sciences of the true, the good, and the 
beautiful (Logic, Ethic, and ^Esthetics). The pre- 
dicates (Existences) originate the sciences which are 
conversant with the effects or results of the creative 
act— namely, Psychology, Cosmology, and the various 
special Physical Sciences. Besides these Rational 
Sciences there are Super-Rational Sciences based on 
revelation ; they are, however, to be classified in the 
same manner as the Rational Sciences. Such is the 
scheme of classification proposed by Gioberti. It 
has various obvious faults, but these it seems unne- 
cessary to specify, seeing that the foundation of the 
whole scheme is utterly untrustworthy. The " ideal 
formula," on which everything is made to depend, is 
admittedly the expression of an act of mystic intui- 
tion, and really an arbitrary affirmation. 



V. FROM WHEWELL TO ZELLER. 

Dr William Whewell, a man of extraordinary wheweii. 
versatility, industry, and knowledge, published in 
1837 a History of the Inductive Sciences, and in 
1840 a Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences. In 
the latter he treated of the classification of the 
sciences. The work was greatly altered, even in 
the arrangement of its parts, in the third edition, 
where the discussion of the problem and the classi- 



198 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

fication proposed will be found in the volume en- 
titled Novum Organon Renovatum, B. II. ch. ix. 
" The classification depends neither upon the facul- 
ties of the mind to which the separate parts of 
our knowledge owe their origin, nor upon the 
objects which each science contemplates, but upon 
a more natural and fundamental element — namely, 
the Ideas which each science involves. The Ideas 
regulate and connect the facts, and are the founda- 
tions of the reasoning, in each science." It is not 
necessary, Dr Whewell observes, that the Idea on 
which a science is founded should be an absolutely 
ultimate principle of thought, or that it should be 
the only Idea involved in the science. "Each 
science may involve, not only the Ideas or Con- 
ceptions which are placed opposite to it in the 
list, but also all which precede it." WhewelTs 
groups of sciences are as follows : 1. Pure Mathe- 
matical Sciences, including Geometry, Arithmetic, 
Algebra, and Differentials, and based on the ideas 
of space, time, number, sign, and limit. 2. Pure 
Motional Sciences, including Pure Mechanism and 
Formal Astronomy, and based on the idea of 
motion. 3. Mechanical Sciences, including Statics, 
Dynamics, Hydrostatics, Hydrodynamics, and Physi- 
cal Astronomy, based on the ideas of force, matter, 
inertia, and fluid pressure, which are modifications 
of the idea of cause. 4. Secondary Mechanical 



FROM WHEWELL TO ZELLER. 199 

Sciences, including Acoustics, Optics, Thermotics, 
and Atmology, and based on the ideas of outness, 
medium of sensation, intensity of qualities, and 
scales of qualities. 5. Analytico-Mechanical Sciences, 
including Electricity, Magnetism, and Galvanism, 
and based on the idea of polarity. This group 
and the immediately preceding one may, it is indi- 
cated, be brought into connection as constituting 
the two branches of Physics. 6. Analytical Science, 
identified with Chemistry, and held to correspond 
with the ideas of element, chemical affinity, and 
substance or atoms. 7. The Analytico-Classifica- 
tory Sciences — namely, Crystallography and Sys- 
tematic Mineralogy, which have symmetry and 
likeness for ideas. 8. The Classificatory Sciences — 
namely, Systematic Botany, Systematic Zoology, 
and Comparative Anatomy, which have as their 
ideas degrees of likeness and natural affinity. 9. 
The Organical Sciences, or Biology, founded on 
the ideas of vital power, assimilation, irritability, 
organisation, and final cause. 10. Metaphysics, 
coincident with Psychology, and corresponding to 
the ideas emotion and thought. 11. The Palsetio- 
logical Sciences, comprehending Geology, Distri- 
bution of plants and animals, Glossology, and 
Ethnography, and springing from the idea of his- 
torical causation. And, 12. Natural Theology, 
which rests on the idea of a first cause. 



200 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

In examining this scheme its fundamental as- 
sumption, that each science presupposes a special 
a priori idea, is by no means found to be borne 
out. Reasons to doubt its truth soon present 
themselves. Suspicion thereof is forced on us by 
Dr Whewell himself, even in regard to the mathe- 
matical sciences. Algebra, for example, rests, he 
tells us, on the a priori idea of sign. But is 
Sign an a priori idea ? And if so, will it not be 
difficult to discover any a posteriori idea ? Natur- 
ally, however, as soon as Dr Whewell passed beyond 
the province of mathematics his difficulties greatly 
increased; and, in fact, with every forward step 
he took the ineptness and inapplicability of the 
principle he had assumed were made more mani- 
fest. He soon reached sciences which he had to 
refer to things never heard of before as a priori 
or fundamental ideas — e.g., fluid pressure, medium 
of sensation, intensity of qualities, polarity, atoms, 
&c. The mental sciences he wisely refrained from 
attempting to subdivide or trace to root ideas. 
There are other serious defects in WhewelTs scheme. 
Thus, Mechanical Science and Analytical or Chemi- 
cal Science have no higher rank assigned them 
than Secondary Mechanical Science and Analytico- 
Mechanical Science; that is to say, they are put 
on a level with sciences which are only branches 
or applications or combinations of themselves. 



FROM WHEWELL TO ZELLER. 201 

Then there follow as Analytico-Classificatory and 
Classificatory Sciences what are simply the un- 
scientific parts of Mineralogy, Botany, and Physi- 
ology. Observation, classification, and description 
of phenomena are not science, although they neces- 
sarily precede it. Anatomy, for instance, regarded 
merely as descriptive, is a subordinate science; it 
is the series of observations and classifications pre- 
paratory to the science of Physiology; it is no 
more a complete science than would be a descrip- 
tion of the lines and figures employed in Geometry. 
Then, tracing the scheme a little farther, we find 
Metaphysics identified with Psychology, which in 
reality amounts to the entire elimination of Meta- 
physics ; and Geology and the Science of the dis- 
tribution of plants and animals appearing, as 
Palaetiological Sciences, after Metaphysics or Psy- 
chology, quite separated from Mineralogy, Botany, 
and Zoology, with which one would naturally have 
expected them conjoined, and with which they are 
certainly in much closer connection than with Meta- 
physics or Psychology. It savours of the ludicrous 
to represent Natural Theology as in closer contact 
with the Palaeontological Sciences than with any 
others, on the ground that they are conversant 
with historical causes and it with the first cause. 
There is, finally, an objection of wider sweep which 
I have not time to work out. Whewell fixes the 



202 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

order of the sciences by referring them to what 
he deems their corresponding ideas. But how has 
he determined the order of the ideas ? And has he 
determined it aright? It would be easy to show 
that he arranged them in a haphazard way, with 
extremely little regard to their rational connections. 

Lubbock. The Remarks on the Classification of the Different 
Branches of Human Knowledge, published in 1838 
by J. W. Lubbock, possess hardly any value. The 
general division of the classification recommended 
is into History, Philosophy, and Fine Arts ; and 
Philosophy is subdivided into Religion, Juris- 
prudence, Intellectual, Moral, and Political Phil- 
osophy, Logic, Mathematics, Natural Philosophy, 
Natural History, Medicine, and Arts, Trade, and 
Manufactures. 

Lindiay. In Progression by Antagonism, published by the 
late Earl of Crawford (when Lord Lindsay) in 1846, 
a "classification of human thought" is put forth 
based on the general theory of development ex- 
pounded in that exceedingly interesting book. 
While the admission is made that no art or 
science springs from imagination alone or reason 
alone, it is also held that each art or science 
must be distinguished by and classed under the 
predominant faculty which originates it. Spirit 
ruling sense predominantly by imagination gives 
rise to Symbolism, Fine Arts, Rhetoric, Poetry, 



FROM WHEWELL TO ZELLER. 203 

and History; ruling predominantly by reason to 
Science, which is Speculative or Pure and Practi- 
cal or Applied, both subdivisible into Physical 
and Metaphysical, each of which contains many 
separate sciences; and ruling by reason and 
imagination in harmonious co-operation to Phil- 
osophy, also to be distributed into Speculative 
and Practical. The order of classification is said 
to be " determinable by that in which the in- 
dividual, national, and universal mind applies 
itself to the respective arts and sciences." 

In 1847 the late Sir George Ramsay published Ramsay. 
A Classification of the Sciences, in Six Tables. 
The primary division is into : 1. Mental Sciences ; 
2. Physical Sciences ; and 3. Mathematics. It does 
not seem to have occurred to the author that, even 
if these were the chief classes of the sciences, the 
order in which they are arranged is the reverse of 
natural. Theology finds a place only under Moral 
Philosophy, one of the mental sciences. The group- 
ing is altogether of an external and unphilosophical 
kind. 

In 1844 Schopenhauer, in the second edition of Schopen 
his chief work, Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung, 
proposed a scheme of distribution of the sciences 
which, perhaps, deserves to be noted only as an 
ingenious curiosity. Schopenhauer, it has been 
said, accepted one of Kant's categories, and threw 



204 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

the other eleven out of the window. It is on his 
one working principle of the sufficient reason that he 
hangs his scheme of classification. Every science 
is regarded as exemplifying predominantly one of 
the forms of that principle. The main division 
is into I. Pure a priori sciences, and II. Empirical 
or a posteriori sciences. The former are subdivided 
into (1) the doctrine of the principle of Being in (a) 
Space — Geometry, and in (6) Time — Arithmetic and 
Algebra; and (2) the doctrine of the principle of 
knowledge — Logic. The latter are concerned with 
the principle of becoming, or law of causality, and 
in its three forms of cause, stimulus, and motive. 
Hence they are grouped as follows : (1) The 
doctrine of causes, (a) General : Mechanics, Hy- 
drodynamics, Physics, Chemistry. (6) Special : 
Astronomy, Mineralogy, Geology, Technology, 
Pharmacy. (2) The doctrine of stimuli (a) General : 
Vegetable and Animal Physiology, with Anatomy 
as auxiliary science. (6) Special : Botany, Zoology, 
Comparative Physiology, Pathology, Therapeutics. 
(3) The doctrine of motives, (a) General : Ethics, 
Psychology. (6) Special : Jurisprudence, History. 

p. E. Dove. Patrick Edward Dove, in his Theory of Human 
Progression (1850), — published at first anonymously, 
but afterward acknowledged, — treated the problem 
under consideration with great clearness and vigour. 



PROM WHEWBLL TO ZBLLER. 205 

The general aim of his work was to show the natural 
probability of the coming of a reign of justice, — the 
advent of a moral millennium, — and, as essential to 
this, to prove that there is a natural progression 
of the mind in the extension of its knowledge and 
the improvement of its practice. Such a progression 
implied, according to Mr Dove, the consecutive evolu- 
tion of the sciences and their logical dependence on 
each other. The classification which he proposed 
rested on the principle that every science must have 
a distinctive object-noun, the place of which among 
the categories of the mind determines the place of 
the science among the series of the sciences. The 
object-noun of a science is the primary condition 
of its existence, and of the forms of that noun the 
science exclusively treats. The connection of object- 
nouns is such that the sciences follow in a deter- 
minate order, the one in which they must necessarily 
be studied and also that in which they must neces- 
sarily be discovered. It is an order of ever-increasing 
complexity, each later science including not only its 
own distinctive concept, but those of all the sciences 
which precede it. Thus, Logic is the first and simplest 
science. Arithmetic is nothing more than Logic 
applied to number. Algebra is Logic and Arithmetic 
applied to quantity. Geometry (in its larger sense) 
is Logic, Arithmetic, and Algebra applied to space. 
Statics is Logic, Arithmetic, Algebra, and Geometry 



206 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

applied to force. And if we look at the object- 
nouns or substantive concepts we shall find, 
according to Mr Dove, that Logic has two branches, 
the one treating of identity and the other of equality; 
that Arithmetic adds to identity and equality num- 
ber; Algebra to identity, equality, and number 
quantity ; Geometry to identity, equality, number, 
and quantity space ; and Statics to all these forces. 
" In this order," we are told, " the mathematical 
sciences must necessarily be classed, and in this 
order the mathematical sciences must necessarily 
be discovered. Ten thousand men originating the 
mathematical sciences by a process of independent 
investigation would necessarily discover them in 
this order ; and were ten thousand worlds peopled 
with human beings to go through the process of 
making anew the mathematical sciences, every one 
of those human races would pass through the same 
intellectual course, and evolve the abstract sciences 
exactly in the same necessary order. The constitu- 
tion of human reason forbids that it should be 
otherwise, one science being impossible until its 
antecedent is so well known as to be capable of 
subjective operation. Thus, unless the laws of 
identity are known, there can be no investigation 
of the laws of equality; and until the laws of 
equality are known, there can be no investigation 
of the laws of number ; and until Arithmetic is 



FROM WHEWELL TO 2ELLEE. 207 

known, there can be no investigation of the laws of 
quantity ; and until the laws of quantity are known, 
there can be no investigation into the relations of 
space ; and until Geometry is known, there can be 
no Statics." 

The sciences which have just been mentioned 
— the mathematical sciences — are all devoid of 
any idea derived from sense. When, however, 
they are applied to the substantives and opera- 
tions of real life, they originate another order of 
sciences — the physical sciences — which arise one 
after another in similar order of complexity. The 
first and simplest of these sciences is Dynamics, 
which is closely connected with the last of the 
mathematical sciences — Statics — Statics dealing 
with forces which neutralise each other, and 
Dynamics with forces which produce motion, the 
simplest and most universal function of matter. It 
is by adding to motion one physical characteristic 
after another that the physical sciences are con- 
secutively evolved. Thus, add to it weight or 
resistance, the next most general property, and you 
have Mechanics ; add still further sound, light, and 
heat, and you have as corresponding sciences 
Acoustics, Optics, and Thermology; add again 
magnetic force, electric force, and affinity, and you 
have the sciences of Magnetism, Electricity, and 
Chemistry; and these three sciences are, in their 



208 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

turn, the necessary preparations for a new, a third 
order of sciences — the sciences of organisation — 
comprehending Vegetable and Animal Physiology. 
These again lead to another, a fourth order of 
sciences, the man -sciences, or sciences of human 
action, which are a sensational and inductive 
science called Political Economy and conversant 
with utility, and a moral and deductive science 
called Politics and conversant with equity. The 
last science is Theology. It closes and completes 
the book of science properly so called. But beyond 
science lies Critical Philosophy. Science is direct 
and spontaneous, and seeks only to determine what 
is true in that which it makes its object, whether 
mind or matter; whereas Philosophy is subjective 
and reflective, and inquires not into the truth of 
thought, but into its form and mechanism, endeav- 
ouring with the whole mass received from the whole 
circle of the sciences to read aright the phenomenon 
of knowledge. 

The scheme of Dove, it will have been remarked, 
has an obvious resemblance to that of Whewell. 
It proceeds throughout on the same assumption, 
although that assumption is applied with much 
greater tact and plausibility by Dove than by 
Whewell. These two objections may be urged 
against the scheme as a whole : 1. The conception 
of object-nouns on which it rests is erroneous. An 



PROM WHEWELL TO ZELLER. 209 

object-noun is implied to be something very different 
from what is ordinarily meant by the object of a 
science — namely, that about which the science is 
conversant; it is supposed to be some single idea 
the application of which to appropriate objects 
constitutes science. But it is only of the purely 
abstract sciences that this can be with any appear- 
ance even of truth maintained. Inductive science 
at least originates in no such way ; it needs only an 
object in the sense of a certain kind of material 
subject to laws discoverable by the inductive 
process. 2. More even than the scheme of Comte 
that of Dove is vitiated by the hypothesis that the 
order of the formation of the sciences is absolutely 
fixed and necessary, proceeding on one straight 
line, and incapable of being other than it is. 
Comte only makes his scheme exclusively rational 
and deductive in the working of it out and by 
taking no account of induction as counteractive of 
deduction, whereas Dove lays down a priori prin- 
ciples and a deductive procedure as the very 
groundwork of his whole system. In so doing 
he builds upon the sand. Reason shows that the 
order of the formation of the sciences must be 
different from what he affirms it to be. Facts 
prove that it is different. Spencer, in his masterly 
criticism of the Comtist classification, has decisively 
established the truth of both of these affirmations. 

o 



210 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

Let us now look a little at the details of Mr 
Dove's scheme. Logic is placed at the head of the 
sciences; it is said to be the first, because the 
simplest, of the sciences. But simplest in this case 
means most abstract, and the most abstract, instead 
of being always first, is generally last. That Logic 
is more abstract than Arithmetic, Algebra, and 
Geometry, instead of being a conclusive reason for 
supposing it to be in the order of study and dis- 
covery before them, is a reason for suspecting it to 
be behind them. And, in fact, both Arithmetic and 
Geometry preceded it. If it be said there can be 
no reasoning in number or space which does not 
presuppose identity and equality, the answer is 
twofold, for, first, in a more relevant sense identity 
and equality presuppose number, space, and other 
concepts regarded as later, since one thing is not 
identical with or equal to another unless identical 
or equal in number, space, &c. ; and, secondly, it 
needs no science to give us the notions of identity 
or equality before we can proceed to study any 
other science, as these notions are firmly and oper- 
atively in our minds before all science. 

Then, further, why confine Logic to reasoning 
in identity and equality? Why not extend it to 
all reasoning? It will be said, because Arithmetic 
is conversant with reasoning in numbers, Algebra 
with reasoning in quantity, Geometry with reason- 



FROM WHEWELL TO ZELLER. 211 

ing in space, &c. But no ; these sciences are con- 
versant with number, quantity, space, and their 
laws, while reasoning and its laws in number, 
quantity, space, or any other concept or matter, 
are the object of Logic, which is therefore not, 
strictly speaking, before any science, but pervasive 
of all science, having to trace the connective 
tissue of all knowledge, the forms and methods 
of all sciences. This view of it, however, would 
have quite deranged Mr Dove's serial arrange- 
ment. It leaves, likewise, no place for his phil- 
osophy; for, according to him, it is Philosophy 
which has to do with the form and method of 
thought. If, therefore, he had taken a sufficiently 
comprehensive view of Logic he would have seen 
that it included and fulfilled all the functions 
which he assigned to Philosophy. 

As to the sciences grouped as Mathematical 
— Arithmetic, Algebra, Geometry, and Statics — it 
is obvious to remark that important mathematical 
sciences are entirely omitted; and that to de- 
scribe Algebra as Logic and Arithmetic applied 
to quantity, or Geometry as Logic, Arithmetic, 
and Algebra applied to space, conveys no meaning, 
and cannot be asserted to be erroneous only be- 
cause unintelligible. Dove represents Arithmetic 
as the first of the mathematical sciences, whereas 
Whewell, it will be remembered, assigns that 



212 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

honour to Geometry. Both are, perhaps, right 
and both wrong. Either science may have origin- 
ated before the other, or they may have been of 
simultaneous origin and growth. Statics is not a 
mathematical science at all. Instead of force being, 
as Dove supposes, a mathematical conception and 
motion, the first and simplest of physical concep- 
tions, it is motion which is the mathematical and 
force which is the physical conception. There is a 
science of pure motion, the science now generally 
called Kinematics ; and it is a mathematical science, 
not only because it treats of motion, displacement, 
and deformature, tortuosity, and curvature, alto- 
gether independently of force, mass, elasticity, 
temperature, magnetism, electricity, which are all 
physical attributes, the first not less than~the last. 
The arrangement of the Physical Sciences is also 
defective. In particular, secondary sciences are put 
on a level or equality of rank with those of which 
they are branches, or at least from which they are 
derived. Passing from the Physical Sciences, Psy- 
chology is found to have been omitted altogether, 
although it must be regarded as the very foundation 
of the so-called Man-Sciences. There can be no 
science of human actions if there be none of human 
nature. Yet Psychology is not merely a Man- 
Science. There is a Comparative Psychology as 
certainly as there is a Comparative Physiology. 



FROM WHEWELL TO ZELLER. 213 

The sphere of Psychology includes every fact of 
sensation, every form of consciousness, animal as 
well as human ; it has to do with the psychical life 
of all sentient creatures from the animalcule to the 
man. This of itself shows that it must always be 
arbitrary to make an exclusive instead of an in- 
clusive group of Man - Sciences. In his Theory 
of Human Progression, Dove ranked Politics or 
Ethics as one of the Man -Sciences, erroneously 
identifying Politics and Ethics. It is curious to 
observe how, in his Elements of Political Science, 
published four years later, he gave Ethics or 
Politics a quite different position. He placed it, 
in this latter treatise, as an abstract science immedi- 
ately after Statics ; in other words, he ranked it as 
a mathematical science, and held that, owing to the 
ideal character of its truths, it stands on a higher 
level than the mental or other inductive sciences. 

M. Couraot, a man of remarkable capacity both Coumot 
for philosophical speculation and scientific research, 
treated of the co-ordination of the departments of 
human knowledge in his Essai sur les fondements 
de nos connaissances (torn. ii. ch. xx.-xxii.), pub- 
lished in 1851. He followed to some extent Bacon, 
and to a much larger extent Amp&re, although he 
also criticised both with characteristic acuteness and 
independence. He may be said to have adopted, 



214 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

in the main, Ampere's classification, but with 
numerous and important modifications which are 
mostly decided improvements. He rejected "the 
artifice of bifurcation." Instead of commingling 
and confounding, as Ampere did, arts and sciences, 
he entirely separated them. He attempted to dis- 
tinguish carefully between science strictly so called 
and history, and founded on the distinction a divi- 
sion of the sciences into two great series — namely, 
(a) a cosmological and historical series and (6) a 
theoretical series. There are thus three parallel 
series of the kinds or divisions of knowledge — a 
technical series, a cosmological and historical series, 
and a theoretical series. Our author did not apply 
the distinction between science and philosophy, like 
that between science and history, as a principle of 
classification. For that his reason was that philos- 
ophy cannot be sharply separated from science, while 
history can. Philosophy, he held, has no special 
object of its own ; is not a science or group or series 
of sciences ; but is an indispensable element of all 
sciences ; lies at their root, pervades their ramifica- 
tions, and reaches to their summits. The series of 
theoretical sciences he divided into five groups — 
the mathematical, physical, biological, noologicaJ, 
and political sciences. Psychology he placed among 
the biological, not the noological sciences; on the 
other hand, he regarded Natural Theology as a 



FROM WHEWELL TO ZELLER. 215 

noological science. Few of his groups seem to com- 
prehend just the sciences which they ought to con- 
tain ; but the distribution as a whole has very great 
merits. 

An American author, Prof. W. D. Wilson, pub- wikon. 
lished in New York, in 1856, an Elementary 
Treatise of Logic, which contains, in its last chapter, 
a classification of both Sciences and Arts. They 
are divided into three classes — namely, Theoretical 
Sciences, Practical Sciences, and Productive Arts; 
so that the scheme is essentially a modernised re- 
production of the Aristotelian distribution of phil- 
osophy. Each of the three classes, we are told, 
" naturally divides itself into two departments, dif- 
fering in the first class, both in the starting-point 
and in the method ; in the second class they differ 
in the starting-point only; and in the third class 
the two departments differ chiefly in the object in 
view — the one producing objects of beauty, and the 
other objects of utility." The departments of the 
Theoretical Sciences are : 1. Exact Sciences, and, 2. 
Pure Sciences. The former includes Meteorology, 
Ouranography, Geology, Geography, Chemistry, 
Mineralogy, Anatomy, Physiology, Botany, Zoology, 
Ethnology, Psychology, and History; the latter 
Arithmetic, Geometry, Algebra, Calculus, Trigono- 
metry, Analytic Geometry, Analytics, Method, and 
Ontology. The departments of the Practical Sciences 



216 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

are: 1. Mixed Sciences, and, 2. Ethical Sciences. 
The former comprehends Mechanics, Astronomy, 
Hydrostatics, Hydraulics, Pneumatics, Acoustics, 
and Optics; the latter Ethics, Polity, Natural Re- 
ligion, Jurisprudence, Church Polity, and Revealed 
Religion. The departments of the Productive Arts 
are : 1. Fine Arts, and 2, Useful Arts. The former 
contains Gardening, Architecture, Sculpture, Paint- 
ing, Music, and Poetry ; and the latter Agriculture, 
Metallurgy, Technology, Typography, Engraving, 
Commerce, Medicine, Rhetoric, Political Economy, 
and War. This scheme is much inferior to that 
of Cournot. It is impossible to regard the order in 
which the sciences are arranged in it as the order 
in which they have been discovered, or that in 
which they should be studied, or as a natural order 
of any kind. A number of the so-called Exact 
Sciences are obviously and necessarily less exact 
than the so-called Pure Sciences and Mixed Sciences. 
The designation Exact Sciences is an infelicitous 
one, as all science is only science on condition of 
being exact. 

There is nothing on our subject worth mentioning 
in the hazy and confused Organismus der Wissen- 
schaft which Adolf Helfferich published in 1856. 
Science he defines as " the rational or ideal repro- 
duction of the real human personality," and, there- 
fore, holds that " the organism (Gliedbau) of science 



FROM WHEWELL TO ZELLER. 217 

must correspond to the organisation (Gliederung) of 
the human being/' 

In Sir Wm. Hamilton's Lectures on Metaphysics, Hamilton, 
published in 1859, but delivered from 1836-37, there 
is a classification (see Lect. VII.) which, although 
comprehending only the mental sciences, may be 
noticed here, because if good for the mental sciences 
it should be equally good for the physical sciences. 
On the other hand, if no physical philosopher would 
think of arranging the sciences with which he is 
conversant as referring to the facts, the laws, and 
the results of the material world, or, in other words, 
as phsenomenological, nomological, and ontological ; 
if, on the contrary, he must recognise that such an 
arrangement would contravene every true notion of 
what science is, it may be inferred that such an 
arrangement of the mental sciences cannot be more 
tenable, less unscientific, less destructive of every 
true notion of the nature of science. Let us con- 
sider, however, Hamilton's classification in itself, 

He starts from the common but erroneons notion 
that philosophy is equivalent to mental science. 
Then he proceeds to divide and distribute philos- 
ophy thus understood on the supposition that mind 
or consciousness yields us facts, laws, and results. 
If we deal merely with the facts or phenomena of 
mind, we have a mental science or department of 
mental science which may be called the Phranomen- 



218 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

ology of Mind, but is generally known as Psy- 
chology. Its divisions correspond to the classes of 
mental phenomena — cognitions, feelings, conative 
powers. If we deal with the laws of mind we have 
a Nomology of Mind, Nomological Psychology, which 
comprises within itself three different Nomologies — 
one of cognition, Logic ; one of feeling, ^Esthetics ; 
and one of conation, Practical Philosophy, or Ethics 
and Politics. If we deal with the results or infer- 
ences which the facts of mind or consciousness 
warrant, we have Ontology, Metaphysics Proper, 
Inferential Psychology. 

Such is the classification of Sir Wm. Hamilton. 
None of its divisions, major or minor, seem to me 
correctly drawn. 

Begin with the first, the Phenomenology of 
Mind, erroneously identified with Psychology. 
What sort of science can that be which deals 
only with facts or phenomena, which deals with 
them to the exclusion of laws ? There can be no 
science where there are no laws. Science consists 
in the knowledge of laws. A mere phsenomen- 
ology, either of matter or mind, however exten- 
sive, however exhaustive, can have no title to be 
deemed science. Psychology is not such a phe- 
nomenology of mind, just because it labours to 
discover the laws of mind, yea, the most hidden, 
the essential, and ultimate laws of mind. The 



PROM WHEWELL TO ZELLER. 219 

separation of facts and laws in science — the assign- 
ing of facts to one science and of laws to another — 
involves not only a false division of the sciences, 
but the mutilation and destruction of the very idea 
and life of science, since science is essentially the 
union of facts and laws, the explanation of facts 
by laws. 

As to the particular divisions of the Nomology, 
not one of them seems accurately drawn. How 
can Logic, for example, be called a Nomology of 
the cognitive powers ? On no reasonable view of 
it, and not even on Sir Wm. Hamilton's own view 
of it. Logic he held to be the science of the formal 
laws of thought, and by thought he meant only 
what is strictly termed discursive thought. In 
other words, he regarded and treated it as the 
science of some of the laws of one of the processes 
of one of the cognitive faculties, yet in his scheme 
of classification represented it to be the science of 
all the laws of all the processes of all the cognitive 
faculties. 

^Esthetics and Ethics are both only in part 
psychological. The distinctive objects and prin- 
ciples of both can no more be evolved out of 
any psychological process than out of any physio- 
logical or other physical process. And, on the 
other hand, the properly psychological province of 
^Esthetics is not inclusive of all the laws of feel- 



220 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

ing, and yet comprehensive of laws of perception, 
imagination, and reason; and the psychological 
provinces of Ethics and Politics are neither limited 
to nor everywhere as extended as the reign of the 
laws of action. 

Then the Inferential Psychology of Sir Wm. 
Hamilton does not seem to answer to Meta- 
physics Proper. Metaphysics is not usually con- 
ceived of as a science of results, but as a science 
of principles. It is almost universally supposed to 
be occupied with the conditions of all science, which 
is a very different thing from consisting of the 
inferences from a particular science. There is a 
science which deals with the results of all other 
sciences — a science to which the ultimate conclu- 
sions of every science are data from which it draws 
its own inferences. That science is Natural Theo- 
logy. When the scientific specialist has reached his 
highest generalisations, the theologian receives them 
from him, and, by showing that they are to be 
regarded as expressions of the manifestation of God- 
head, surrounds them with a halo of Divine glory. 
Metaphysics is quite a different science, being con- 
versant not with what thus overlies, but with 
what underlies our knowledge of contingent things. 
Hence Sir Wm. Hamilton's description of Meta- 
physics answers not at all to Metaphysics, but 
slightly to Natural Theology. And it will be ob- 



FROM WHEWELL TO ZELLER. 221 

served that both the instances which he gives as 
specimens of the inferences with which Metaphysics 
is concerned are not metaphysical, but theological 
truths — the existence of God and the immortality 
of the soul. But while Hamilton's Metaphysics 
answers slightly to Natural Theology, it is only 
slightly and badly, seeing that the truths of Natural 
Theology ought to be drawn from the results not of 
psychological science alone, but of all science. All 
things tell us of God. The mind, indeed, always 
draws the inference which relates to Him, but it 
does not always draw it from itself. Further, Sir 
Wm. Hamilton's Inferential Psychology, as described 
by himself, is not a psychological science, is not a 
division of Psychology. Its inferences relate to 
realities beyond the mind, while explanatory of 
mind; its truths are reached through truths of 
Psychology, but are not truths of Psychology. Sir 
Wm. Hamilton's classification, in fact, is erroneous 
from beginning to end — erroneous in its root and in 
all its ramifications. 

The late M. Charles Renouvier, a vigorous and Renouyiar. 
acute thinker who developed and applied the doc- 
trine of phenomenalism with a comprehensiveness 
and consistency probably unequalled, dealt with the 
subject of the rational classification of the sciences 
in the second of his Essais de Critique G4nSrcUe 9 



222 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

the TraitS de Psychohgie Rationnelle (ch. xviiL), 
first published in 1859. 1 He entirely rejected 
Comtek hypothesis of a hierarchy of the sciences, 
and regarded their classification as purely a question 
of logical arrangement. He describes what he calls 
General Criticism (La Critique GSnSrate) as "the 
common trunk of all the sciences." It has to 
analyse the universal conditions of knowledge ; to 
study the general nature and laws of experience ; 
and to treat specially of the categories of relation, 
personality, causality, and finality. From this trunk 
spring two great branches of sciences — the logical 
and the physical — which differ not only in their 
objects, but also in their methods, the logical 
sciences following the method of ratiocination, and 
the physical sciences the method of observation and 
experimentation. The logical sciences comprehend 
(a) logical sciences in the narrower sense of the 
word, those occupied with the relations of quality 
— namely, Logic and General Grammar; and (6) 
mathematical sciences, those occupied with the 
categories of number, position, succession, and 
change — namely, Arithmetic, Algebra, Mathemati- 
cal Analysis, Geometry, Rational Mechanics, and 
Applied Mathematics. The physical sciences in- 
clude a group of Natural History Sciences (Cos- 
mology, Geology, Mineralogy, Botany, Zoology, 

1 I have seen only the second edition, which is of 1875. 



FROM WHEWELL TO ZELLER. 223 

and their subsidiary disciplines), Physics (with 
Astronomy appended), Chemistry, and Biology. 
The main line of demarcation among the physical 
sciences is that which has strictly physical science 
and chemical science on the one side, and biological 
science on the other, just as the great division of 
their objects is into inorganic and organic. There 
are, however, according to Renouvier, a number of 
other studies which are not yet definitively separated 
from philosophical speculation and constituted dis- 
tinct sciences. These, therefore, he would not class 
as sciences, but regard as belonging to General 
Criticism. They include History, Morals, Politics, 
and Political Economy, and were they sufficiently 
advanced to be accounted sciences might be classed 
as Moral Sciences. The tree of science would then 
have three, not two, great branches. 

The foregoing scheme has, I think, serious defects. 
One is the non-recognition of theological science. 
It is due, doubtless, to the thoroughness and con- 
sistency of M. Renouvier's phenomenalism; but 
it also indicates that an exclusive phenomenalism 
is not the whole truth. Then, what M. Renouvier 
calls General Criticism seems an incoherent and 
incongruous combination of philosophy and special 
science. It is identified both with the knowledge 
which transcends special science because of its 
universality, and with that which falls below it 



224 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

because of its lack of certainty. That is not a 
view to be commended. Philosophy should keep 
to the universal, and cannot be too critical; and 
it shows itself forgetful of both requirements when 
it identifies itself with special studies on the ground 
that they are somewhat too conjectural and un- 
critical to be deemed sciences. It may, further, 
be reasonably objected that the conditions of 
thought and their relations ought to be regarded 
as the objects, not of La Critique GenSrale, but 
of a special science with a perfectly definite sphere 
— a science closely akin to, if not inclusive of, 
Logic, which treats of the conditions of a kind of 
thought, discursive thought; also, that Logic has 
to do with reasoning in quantity as well as in 
quality, and, indeed, with reasoning in all cate- 
gories and under all forms. A glance at the order 
in which the physical sciences are arranged will 
suggest that Comte's view of "a hierarchy of the 
sciences " cannot be so wholly false as M. Renouvier 
contends. Were it not on the whole a natural and 
true view he would hardly be found conforming 
to it so much, even when condemning it. It is, 
likewise, certainly a serious defect in the scheme 
that so many sciences are left unclassed and un- 
arranged. Notwithstanding his great ability, there- 
fore, M. Renouvier was not in this instance quite 
successful. 



FROM WHEWELL TO ZELLER. 225 

In a tractate entitled Nuovo Albero Eneiclo- Pecoenini 
pedico, published at Naples in 1863, Melchiore 
Peccenini, of Ferrara, has classified the sciences 
on the hypothesis that the three chief endowments 
of mind are the intellect, the will, and the aesthetic 
sentiment, and that the objects which respectively 
correspond to them are truth, goodness, and beauty. 
Truth, goodness, and beauty are naturally and 
closely connected, and equally so are all the sciences 
and fine arts, seeing that they originate in these 
innate ideas. Common to all the sciences and arts 
is being (Vente), which in relation to intellect is 
truth, in relation to will goodness, and in relation 
to aesthetic sense and imagination beauty. Hence, 
under the head of "Truth (Intellect)" are placed 
all the sciences which "regard being purely with 
reference to intelligence." Thus, abstract being is 
said to be the object of Ontology or Protology; 
concrete being in God of Natural and Revealed 
Theology ; concrete being in the soul of Psychology, 
Ideology, Logic, Grammar, and Somatics ; and con- 
crete being in matter of General Physics and Par- 
ticular Physics, both of which are inclusive of a 
large number of sciences. Under " Goodness (Will)" 
are arranged the sciences "which relate to being 
as fitted to satisfy the wants of the spirit." These 
are Eudemonology, Moral Philosophy, and Juris- 
prudence, with its various subordinate and sub- 

p 



226 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

8idiary disciplines. Under "Beauty (^Esthetic 
sentiment)" are classed the sciences "which refer 
to being as capable of gratifying the spirit and 
senses." These are ^Esthetics, which treats of 
abstract beauty, and a number of sciences which 
deal with concrete beauty as exemplified in forms, 
motions, sounds, and words. Such is the classi- 
fication of Signor Peccenini. I believe that neither 
its metaphysical nor its psychological principle will 
stand examination. Placing the physical sciences 
after the theological and psychological sciences is 
in various respects obviously unnatural. Not one 
of the larger groups seems accurately divided and 
distributed. 

DiGio- In 1863 appeared also the first edition of Prof. 

Di Giovanni's Principii di Filosqfia Prima (the 
2nd ed. is of 1878), in which (vol. i. Lez. 3) the 
sciences are classified as belonging either to Primary 
or Secondary Philosophy. The former is repre- 
sented as comprehending Logic, Ontology, Theology, 
Cosmology, Psychology, Noology, and Ethics; the 
latter as containing ^Esthetics, Philosophy of 
Systems, Social Philosophy, and Philosophy of 
History. The learned author endeavoured to 
show that his classification can be connected 
with, and conformed to, the ideal formula of 
Gioberti. 



FROM WHEWELL TO ZELLER. 227 

Herbert Spencer's essay on The Genesis of Herbert 
Science, originally published in 1854, was largely 
devoted to the refutation of Comte's views re- 
garding the rational arrangement of the sciences. 
His own views as to their correlation were ex- 
pounded in a subsequent essay on The Classifica- 
tion of the Sciences, originally published in 1864 ; 
and obviously opposition to Comte must have been 
a considerable motive and factor in their forma- 
tion. He held that "the sciences as arranged 
in the succession specified by M. Comte do not 
logically conform to the natural and invariable 
hierarchy of phenomena " ; that " there is no serial 
order whatever in which they can be placed, which 
represents either their logical dependence or the 
dependence of phenomena " ; and that "the his- 
torical development of the sciences has not taken 
place in any serial order." At the same time, he 
thought that the sciences may be distributed into 
classes, and endeavoured to show how that may be 
done on what he regarded as the only true principle 
of classification — namely, that in each class of colli- 
gated facts more numerous and radical character- 
istics must be included than any of its facts have 
in common with objects excluded from the class. 
Now, having regard to this principle, the broadest 
natural division of the sciences is, he affirmed, that 
between sciences which deal with the abstract rela- 



228 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

tions under which phenomena are presented to us, 
and those which deal with the phenomena them- 
selves — between sciences which deal with the mere 
blank forms of existence, and those which deal with 
real existences. The former class contains Logic and 
Mathematics, and these are pre-eminently the Ab- 
stract Sciences. The latter class is composed of two 
great groups of sciences, the Abstract Concrete 
Sciences and the Concrete Sciences. The Abstract 
Concrete Sciences treat of realities in their ele- 
ments, or of the real relations implicated in certain 
classes of facts. Such are Mechanics, Physics, and 
Chemistry. The Concrete Sciences deal with reali- 
ties in their totalities, or, in other words, with aggre- 
gates of phenomena. They comprehend Astronomy, 
Geology, Biology, Psychology, and Sociology. 
"From the beginning, the abstract sciences, the 
abstract concrete sciences, and the concrete sciences 
have progressed together, the first solving problems 
which the second and third presented, and growing 
only by the solution of the problems; and the 
second similarly growing by joining the first in 
solving the problems of the third. All along there 
has been a continuous action and reaction between 
the three great classes of sciences." 

The classification of Mr Spencer has been criti- 
cised by Bain in his Deductive Logic, by Renouvier 
in his Psychologies by Siciliani in his Rinnovamento 



FROM WHEWELL TO ZELLER. 229 

della Filosofia positiva in Italia, and others. It 
has been adopted with some modifications by Mr 
Fiske in his Cosmic Philosophy. It has been de- 
fended against the objections of Dr Bain by Mr 
Spencer himself in the third edition of his essay 
(1871). My own criticism of it must necessarily 
be much briefer than I could wish. 

Mr Spencer was probably right in holding that 
any merely serial arrangement of the sciences must 
be an inadequate and erroneons expression of their 
relations to one another. But he can hardly have been 
correct in supposing that there is no natural series 
of the sciences at all — none representative either of 
logical dependence or dependence of phenomena. 
In fact, he himself recognised a truth which plainly 
implied that sciences may be arranged in series 
according to their logical dependence. Mark the 
following words : — 

The three groups of Sciences may be briefly defined as 
laws of the forms, laws of the factors, laws of the products. 
And when thus defined, it becomes manifest that the groups 
are so radically unlike in their natures that there can be no 
transitions between them ; and that any Science belonging to 
one of the groups must be quite incongruous with the Sciences 
belonging to either of the other groups, if transferred. 
How fundamental are the differences between them will be 
further seen on considering their functions. The first, or 
abstract group, is instrumental with respect to both the 
others ; and the second, or abstract-concrete group, is instru- 



230 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

mental with respect to the third or concrete group. An 
endeavour to invert these functions will at once show how 
essential is the difference of character. The second and 
third groups supply subject-matter to the first, and the 
third supplies subject-matter to the second ; but none of the 
truths which constitute the third group are of any use as 
solvents of the problems presented by the second group ; 
and none of the truths which the second group formulates 
can act as solvents of problems contained in the first group. 

In that passage we are told that the abstract 
sciences, Logic and Mathematics, are instrumental 
to the abstract - concrete sciences, Mechanics, 
Physics, and Chemistry, and that all these sciences 
of both classes are instrumental not only to such 
concrete sciences as deal only with mathematical, 
mechanical, physical, and chemical properties — e.g., 
Astronomy and Geology, but also to those which 
are conversant with distinctly new peculiarities — 
e.g., Biology and Psychology. But if so, on 
what ground could Mr Spencer maintain that the 
sciences of Logic, Mathematics, Mechanics, Physics, 
Chemistry, Biology, and Psychology do not form 
a logically dependent series? Is Logic not as 
instrumental to Mathematics as Mathematics to 
Mechanics or Physics? Is Physics not as instru- 
mental to Chemistry as Chemistry to Biology? 
How could Mr Spencer contend that Biology is not 
instrumental to Psychology, seeing that he repre- 
sented both as sciences of the same class ? Astro- 



PROM WHEWELL TO ZELLER. 231 

nomy and Geology, however certain and soundly 
constituted sciences they may be, cannot possibly 
be ranked among sciences which deal with elements 
or properties not resolved, or proved to be resolv- 
able, into properties with which more general 
sciences are occupied. But these two sciences being 
removed from where they have plainly no right to 
be, Mr Spencer would seem to have himself con- 
structed a series of sciences of the very kind which, 
in opposition to Comte, he declared to be impos- 
sible. Comte meant no more by calling one science 
logically dependent on another than that the one 
placed first is instrumental as regards the one 
placed last, while the latter is not instrumental 
as regards the former. If there be a number of 
sciences dealing with fundamentally distinct pheno- 
mena, and so related that every antecedent is 
instrumental as regards every consequent, and no 
consequent is instrumental as regards any ante- 
cedent, a series of sciences is constituted which 
represents the logical dependence of its members. 
Mr Spencer started with denying that there was 
any such series, but ended by implicitly showing 
that there was one. His own classification, taken 
in connection with the passage quoted, was a 
decisive refutation of what was extreme in his own 
criticism of the Comtist scheme. So far from 
having succeeded in overthrowing that scheme, he 



232 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

only at the utmost succeeded in slightly modifying 
it. There is a logical dependence of the sciences. 
And why ? Just because there is a natural depend- 
ence of phenomena. The quantitative relations 
with which mathematics deals are more general 
than the mechanical laws which physics brings to 
light; there can be no chemical combinations un- 
conditioned by physical properties ; vital functions 
never appear apart from chemical processes; and 
there must be life before there can be consciousness. 
That remarkable hierarchy of phenomena is a fact 
which a cloud of abstract language or a covering of 
subtle reasoning may to some extent and for a short 
while conceal from our view, but which no language 
or reasoning can efface or even long obscure. And 
there being such a hierarchy of phenomena, it is 
scarcely conceivable that there should be no corre- 
sponding hierarchy of sciences. 

The terminology of the Spencerian classification 
has little to recommend it. There is no science 
which deals with concrete things to the exclusion of 
abstract relations or with abstract relations to the 
exclusion of concrete things. All science deals with 
relations, and is more or less abstract. The con- 
creteness of the objects of the so-called concrete 
sciences is a concretion of elements and laws which 
are abstract; and the essential function of these 
sciences is to discover the abstract factors and 



FBOM WHEWELL TO ZELLER. 233 

operations explanatory of the concrete wholes. 
Triangles, squares, and circles are as much concrete 
things with respect to space and its relations as the 
earth is a concrete thing with respect to matter and 
its physical properties and laws. The only distinc- 
tion among the sciences as to abstractness is one of 
more or less ; the only difference one of degree and 
not of kind. It should be obvious, from the very 
nature of abstraction, that the word abstract is so 
entirely a term of degree and relation that it cannot 
be properly employed to denote distinctions deemed 
ultimate or specific. But Mr Spencer's use of it 
was not merely inappropriate; it was misleading, 
inasmuch as it tended to conceal from view that 
the chief requirement in a philosophical classifica- 
tion of the sciences is to determine which are simple 
and fundamental, and which compound and deriva- 
tive. Comte clearly saw the importance of that 
requirement ; Spencer, unfortunately, did not see it, 
and so threw together into his third group sciences 
which are really separated by the deepest and 
widest of scientific distinctions. 

Mr Spencer's reasons for affirming that the so- 
called abstract sciences, Logic and Mathematics, are 
more widely separated from all others than any 
other sciences are from one another, are far from 
convincing. One is that these abstract sciences 
deal with relations apart from realities, whereas 



234 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

other sciences deal with realities, and " relations of 
whatever orders are nearer akin to one another than 
they are to any objects, and objects of whatever 
orders are nearer akin to one another than they are 
to any relations." That Mr Spencer supposed to be 
self-evident. It is not so. Moral relations are 
surely much more akin to moral actions than to 
mathematical relations. If not, there should be a 
science of moral relations parted by a wide chasm 
from a science of moral actions. Were Mr Spencer's 
view correct, the division among the sciences into 
sciences of relations and sciences of objects should 
be drawn through the whole scheme of science, 
instead of being merely made use of to separate two 
sciences from the rest. In fact, it is quite incorrect, 
and no division of the sciences ought to be founded 
upon it. There is no science without both objects 
and relations. There are no relations without objects. 
The conception of relations without objects is not 
an abstract, but an absurd conception. What proof 
did Mr Spencer produce that the abstract sciences 
deal exclusively with relations? None at all; he 
merely said that they deal exclusively with space 
and time, and that "space is the abstract of all 
relations of coexistence, and time the abstract of all 
relations of sequence." But how can there be any 
relations of coexistence without space, or of rela- 
tions of sequence without time ? Every experience 



FROM WHEWELL TO ZELLER. 235 

and conception of coexistence presupposes the 
intuition of space, and of sequence that of time. 
To call the necessary conditions of thought and 
experience abstracts from either is a serious abuse 
of language. Mr Spencer had, however, another 
reason for regarding his first division of the 
sciences as the broadest which can be drawn. 
The abstract sciences, he said, treat of "the 
forms in which phenomena are known to us," 
" the empty forms of things," whereas other 
sciences treat of "the phenomena themselves," 
"things themselves"; and "the distinction be- 
tween the empty forms of things and the things 
themselves is a distinction which cannot be 
exceeded in degree." Things, things themselves, 
are, then, phenomena, phenomena themselves — 
not noumena, or things in themselves. One is 
glad to know that, for the word "thing" is by 
itself very vague and nebulous; but knowing it, 
one must wish to know also what Mr Spencer 
can mean by contrasting space and time with 
things or phenomena. Are these "forms of 
things" not themselves "things"? Are these 
" forms of phenomena " not themselves " phe- 
nomena " ? Yes or no ? If yes, why oppose 
forms and things, forms and phenomena ? If no, 
then there are sciences of what are not things, 
of what are not phenomena — sciences either of 



236 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

nothings or noumena — and, in that case, Mr 
Spencer's whole philosophy was a vanity, inas- 
much as it was based on the supposition that 
science is limited to the phenomenal. Further, 
one may reasonably wish to know in what relevant 
sense Mr Spencer could call space and time " empty 
forms." If they are empty, how do the sciences 
which deal with them bring so much out of them ? 
Ex nihilo nihil fit. It is manifestly just because 
space and time are not empty of quantitative pro- 
perties and relations that there are mathematical 
sciences ; and manifestly just because they are 
thus not empty, but contain so many of the 
fundamental attributes of matter, that the sway 
of mathematical science is spreading over the 
whole physical universe, and that physical 
science tends constantly to become more and 
more mathematical. 

I might proceed to show by a direct considera- 
tion of the abstract and abstract-concrete sciences 
of Mr Spencer that the distance between them is 
by no means so broad as he affirmed, but that 
has been already so successfully accomplished by 
other critics as to be now unnecessary. The 
abstract sciences, according to Mr Spencer, were 
Logic and Mathematics; and the former treated 
of qualitative, the latter of quantitative relations. 
That Logic treats of qualitative relations was, 



FROM WHEWELL TO ZELLER. 237 

however, a proposition which he not only- 
failed to substantiate, but failed to make intelli- 
gible. He regarded it as conversant in some 
sense, like Mathematics, with time and space. 
What, then, are the qualitative, non-quantitative 
relations either of time or space? Logic is not 
limited in the way Mr Spencer supposed. Were 
it unable to deal with quantitative relations there 
could be no Mathematics. There is even no 
perfectly accurate Logic which is not quanti- 
tative. Logic if simply qualitative may be con- 
clusive, but cannot be absolutely exact. 

Mr Spencer's distribution of the abstract-concrete 
sciences into Mechanics, Physics, Chemistry, and 
Sciences of Light, Heat, Electricity, and Magnet- 
ism seems inferior to Comte's classification of the 
fundamental sciences, if Astronomy be excluded. 
Biology and Psychology, if not Sociology, ought 
to find their places in this group and not among 
the merely concrete sciences, as although they 
have concrete applications, they are in their own 
natures decidedly abstract. There are important 
differences between Mechanics and Physics, or 
rather between Molar and Molecular Mechanics; 
but it is very doubtful if we ought to regard 
them as two distinct kinds of Mechanics, or two 
fundamentally distinct sciences. To do so appears 
an error akin to Comte's separation of Celestial 



238 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

from Terrestrial Mechanics. How objectionable 
the designation " abstract -concrete" is may be 
most readily seen, perhaps, in the case of 
Mechanics, which in itself is as abstract as 
Geometry, and in its applications is not more 
concrete. 

The distinction between the so-called abstract- 
concrete and concrete sciences implies a real dis- 
tinction, but does not coincide with it. The 
division which should have been drawn is that 
between fundamental or simple and derivative or 
complex sciences. If, instead of Biology and 
Psychology, Mr Spencer had inserted Botany 
and Zoology into his third group, he would have 
conformed much better to his own description of 
concrete science, and would have ranked along 
with Astronomy and Geology sciences which 
resemble them much more in scope, method, 
and general character. 

Like Comte, Mr Spencer failed to recognise 
how broad is the division between physical and 
psychical science; like Comte also, he assigned 
no place in the system of knowledge either to 
Metaphysics or Theology. These peculiarities of 
opinion followed naturally from his principles, 
but must, of course, appear serious defects to 
those whose principles are different. 



PROM BAIN TO WUNDT. 239 

The discourse of Prof. Zeller, Ueb$r die Aufgabe Zeiier. 
der Philosophie und ihre Stellung zu den ubrigen 
Wissenschaften, held at Heidelberg on 23rd Nov- 
ember 1868, 1 touches thoughtfully on our problem 
at various points, but does not directly treat of 
it. The important work of the late Prof. Harms, 
Philosophische Einleitung in die Encyklopaedie 
der Physik y which forms the first volume of 
Karsten's Allgemeine Encyclopaedia der Physik, 
and was published in 1869, does not classify or 
distribute the non-physical sciences. 



VI. PROM BAIN TO WUNDT. 

The late Dr Alex. Bain of Aberdeen in the first Bain, 
division of his Logic — the volume devoted to 
Deduction, and published in 1870 — has dealt with 
the classification of the sciences with characteristic 
ability. He started with the affirmation that 
Science is the perfect form of knowledge, and 
thus indicated its peculiarities : " It employs special 
means and appliances to render knowledge true, is 
knowledge made as general as possible, embraces 
a distinct department of the world, or groups 

1 Republished in his Vartriige u. Abhancttungen. Zweite Samm- 
lung, 1877. 



240 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

together facts and generalities that are of a kindred 
sort, and has a certain order or arrangement of 
topics, suitable to its ends, in gathering, in verify- 
ing, and in communicating knowledge." Then, 
accepting as primary and fundamental Comte's 
division of the Sciences into Abstract and Concrete, 
he described the former as the truly fundamental 
sciences, and as bound to precede the latter. 
Logic, Mathematics, Mechanics or Mechanical 
Physics, Molecular Physics, Chemistry, Biology, 
and Psychology, are what he held to be the funda- 
mental sciences. " In every one of these," he has 
said, " there is a distinct department of phenomena ; 
taken together they comprehend all known pheno- 
mena; and the order indicated is the order from 
simple to complex, and from independent to 
dependent, marking the order of study and evolu- 
tion ; " and, further, that, taken collectively, " they 
contain the laws of every known process in the 
world, whether of matter or of mind ; and set 
forth these laws in the order suitable for studying 
and comprehending them to the greatest possible 
advantage. No phenomenon can be strange to any 
one thoroughly conversant with these subjects." 
In Appendix A he has treated very briefly the 
classifications of Bacon, D'Alembert, Neil Arnott, 
but very carefully that of Herbert Spencer. The 
first five, indeed, are disposed of in a few lines. 



FROM BAIN TO WUNDT. 241 

The criticism of Spencer's scheme seems to me 
to be a quite adequate and very conclusive study. 
So far as I am aware, it has not been answered. 
Part II. — the vol. on Induction — treats in Book 
V. of the 'Logic of the Sciences' (pp. 193-367). 
Here Logic seems to be represented as so absorbed 
in the other fundamental sciences as not to be itself 
a science, or the first of the sciences, or in possession 
of a specific method of its own no less than other 
sciences. Epistemology, on the other hand, appears 
to be left out of account. But how can that be 
justified ? Apparently Logic should be preceded by 
and included in Epistemology rather than the latter 
should be absorbed in the former. Dr Bain has 
dwelt instructively on the notions, propositions, 
definitions, and axioms of Mathematics. His 
divisions of Mathematics are — (1) Arithmetic, (2) 
Algebra, (3) Geometry, (4) Algebraic Geometry, 
which furnishes rules for the embodiment and 
interpretation of formulae, and (5) the Higher 
Calculus, which deals with incommensurable quan- 
tities. Mathematics is followed by Physics, and 
Physics is divided into the Physics of Masses 
(Molar Physics) and the Physics of Molecules 
(Molecular Physics). Molar Physics is represented 
as having Abstract and Concrete Branches. The 
Abstract Branches comprise — Mathematics of 
Motion (Kinematics) ; Forces in equilibrio (Statics), 

Q 



242 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES, 



and Forces causing motion (Dynamics), The Con- 
crete Branches are — Mechanic Powers and Solid 
Machinery, Hydrostatics and Hydro - dynamics, 
Aerostatics and Piwumat tics and A 

\y (pp. 222-233), Molecular Physics assumes 
mams of matter to be composed of atoms or 
molecules that attract or repel each other in various 
modes, and in consequence of which its chief sub- 
jects are Attractions (Cohesion, &c), Heat, Light, 
and Electricity (pp, 233-243). Chemistry follows 
directly on Physics, and ia intimately related to 
all the departments of Molecular Physics. It is 
divided into Inorganic and Organic (pp. 242-257). 
Biology is placed immediately after Chemistry, 
defined as the science of living bodies, all such 
bodies being constituted from elements common 
to them all, Under that head the structure, 
functions, various distinctive notions, methods, and 
hypotheses of Biology are treated of {pp. 258-275). 
Psychology is represented as the last of the Ab- 
stract Sciences ; as comprehensive of both animal 
and human mind ; and so intimately related alike 
to body and mind that they are always concomitant, 
and every fact of mind has two sides, a mental and 
a physical. The Science of Character is presup- 
posed by and conjoined with that of Mind. The 
account of Psychology (pp, 275-286) is throughout 
remarkably clear and instructive, and so likewise. 



FROM BAIN TO WUNDT. 243 

although more briefly, what is said of the Science 
of Character (pp. 286-290). 

Besides the Fundamental or Abstract Sciences 
there are also in the scheme of Dr Bain Dependent 
and Concrete Sciences. There are further distinc- 
tively ' sciences of classification/ which include not 
only Mineralogy, Botany, and Zoology (see Part 
II., pp. 292-314), but also Meteorology, Geography, 
Sociology, and Philology (Part I., p. 28). Dr Bain 
seems to have forgotten, when occupied with Part 
II., what he had written in Part I. In self-con- 
sistency his list of Concrete Sciences should have 
included seven sciences, — the four in Part I. as 
well as the three in Part II. Of all the Concrete 
Sciences he maintained that " no one of them 
involves any operation but what is expounded in 
the fundamental or departmental sciences." 

Finally, Bain has included in his scheme Practical 
Sciences. These form not only a large but a most 
heterogeneous group, including arts like Building 
and Dyeing, disciplines like Jurisprudence and 
Political Economy, and sciences which may fairly 
be held to be themselves fundamental and depart- 
mental, as, for example, Economics, Ethics, and 
^Esthetics. That group is no natural class but 
an artificial and heterogeneous conglomeration, to 
which may be added all sorts of occupations, as, 
e.g., Baking, Brewing, and the like. Like Comte 



244 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

and Spencer, Dr Bain has acknowledged neither 
Metaphysics nor Theology to be sciences of any 
kind. For that view I have never found good 
reasons given. The opinion has been always rested 
mainly on misconceptions as to what Metaphysics 
and Theology are, and also as to what should be 
understood by the terms knowledge, science, and 
philosophy. Leaving out of account Dr Bain's un- 
satisfactory conception as to what should be called 
i Practical Sciences,' his classification of the sciences 
properly so called may well be regarded as an im- 
provement on Comte's and much superior to 
Spencer's. 

Cantoni. Prof. Carlo Cantoni, well known by his remark- 
able studies on Vico and Kant, and the most 
emhient representative of Neo-Kantian criticists, 
also sketched a classification of the sciences in his 
Corso elementare di Filosofia, — a work published 
in the same year as Bain's, and which has gone 
through at least ten editions. He would divide 
the sciences, according to the nature of the cogni- 
tions which constitute them, into two classes — the 
ideal or rational and the experimental. And he 
would further divide them according to their matter 
or objects into three classes — namely, 1. Those 
which treat of the fundamental principle and uni- 
versal conditions of existence — Ontology, Natural 



FROM BAIN TO WUNDT. 245 

Theology, Cosmology ; 2. Those which treat of 
material things and conditions — Physics, Chem- 
istry, Natural History, Mathematics ; and 3. Those 
which treat of the powers, laws, and actions of 
spiritual beings, i.e., men — Psychology, Logic, Ethic, 
^Esthetic, Philosophy of Law, Philosophy of His- 
tory, and Paedagogy. Whatever merits this scheme 
may have it may also be held to be defective in 
that it does not recognise the necessary conjunc- 
tion of the ideal and experimental in cognition, nor 
the unnaturalness of placing first the sciences which 
are most remote and abstruse, nor the error of 
treating fundamental and derivative sciences as of 
co-ordinate rank. 

The first edition of Prof. Valdarnini's Principio Vaidar- 
Intendimento e Storia della Classificazione delle 
umane conoscenze secondo Franceso Bacone also 
appeared in 1870. The second edition is of 1880. 
It contains a skilful exposition and energetic de- 
fence of the Baconian classification, and gives a 
brief but meritorious account of a number of other 
classifications of the sciences. 

G. B. Peyretti, who has drawn his philosophy PeyrettL 
largely from Rosmini, discourses of the evolution 
and distribution of the sciences in his Istituzioni 
di Filosqfia teoretica, published at Turin in 1874. 
The fundamental division of his classification is 
into rational or human sciences, which are con- 



246 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

versant with the intelligible; and revealed or 
divine sciences, conversant with the superinteU 
ligible. Each of these orders is divided into a 
scienza prima and scienze seconde. The primary 
science supplies to the secondary sciences appro- 
priate principles, and may be regarded as the 
organising and organic whole of which the second- 
ary sciences are the members. The primary rational 
science is Philosophy, which is either Theoretical 
(inclusive of Ideology and Metaphysics) or Prac- 
tical. The secondary rational sciences are Mathe- 
matics, Physics, Chemistry, Mineralogy, Botany, 
Zoology, Medicine, Jurisprudence, &c. Theology 
is said to be the primary revealed science, and 
Dogmatic Theology and Moral Theology the 
secondary revealed sciences. 

The separation of the intelligible and superin- 
telligible, of philosophy and theology, of rational 
and revealed sciences, as presented in that scheme, 
implies a very perplexing dualism which Peyretti 
attempts to transcend by the supposition of "a 
science of the whole, both intelligible and super- 
intelligible — a synthesis of the sciences " — Encyclo- 
paedia. But must not such Encyclopaedia be 
deemed the only true scienza prima, and Philo- 
sophy and Theology only scienze seconde? Be- 
sides, how is the synthesis to be effected? Is it 
by reason or revelation ? In either case reason 



FROM BAIN TO WUNDT. 247 

and revelation must stand to each other in another 
relation than is implied in the contrast which de- 
mands a synthesis. The classification of Peyretti 
unfortunately rests on conceptions of the relation 
of reason to truth and science, and of nature to 
revelation, which must render it unacceptable to 
all but a small class of religionists, and are too 
likely to lead others to undervalue the really judi- 
cious observations which he has made on the forms 
of knowledge and the stages of its development. 

Baldassare Labanca, Professor of the Science of Labanca. 
Eeligions in the University of Eome, has written 
many most interesting philosophical works and a 
still greater number which deal with religious 
questions. Any student of theology would find 
it well worth the trouble of acquiring a knowledge 
of Italian, were it only that he might be able to 
read the works of Labanca. Of course, his classi- 
fication of the sciences is all that here concerns 
us. He advocates what he calls an inclusive 
system of philosophy, in opposition to exclusive 
systems, devotes a chapter of his Dialettica (vol 
ii. lib. iv. c. L), published in 1875, to a considera- 
tion of the proper encyclopaedical arrangement of 
the sciences. In his view, a logical distribution of 
truth must be the basis of a logical distribution of 
the sciences, seeing that truth is the end of all the 



248 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

sciences. But that is threefold. All truth comes 
from the ideal world, the real world, or the social 
world, and is apprehended through reason, sensi- 
bility, or testimony. Hence three classes of sciences 
— the speculative, experimental, and documental. 

To the speculative class belong the metaphysical, 
mathematical, ethical, juridical, political, and aesthet- 
ical sciences ; to the experimental class, all the 
sciences called positive — physics, mechanics, chem- 
istry, geology, &c. ; to the documental class, the 
historical, linguistic, geographical, statistical, and 
economical sciences. All sciences, however, assume 
certain principles and primary data, and so presup- 
pose and depend on Philosophy. The divisions of 
philosophy correspond to those of science ; hence, 
a philosophy of spirit, comprehensive of the ideal 
or speculative sciences ; a philosophy of nature, 
regulative of the positive or experimental sciences ; 
and a philosophy of history, which dominates the 
documental or social sciences. These three great 
branches of philosophy spring from a primary and 
universal philosophy, the one root and common 
stem of the tree of knowledge. 

Is that scheme as true and solid as it is neat 
and symmetrical ? No ; and for a reason fully 
acknowledged by Signor Labanca himself. He 
tells us that he bases his fundamental division 
merely on the predominance of the traits men- 



FROM BAIN TO WUNDT. 249 

tioned, not on the exclusion of others; that the 
speculative sciences cannot dispense with experi- 
ence and authority, or the positive sciences with 
reason and authority, or the social sciences with 
reason and experience ; and that all the sciences 
are, in fact, mixed, being drawn more or less 
from all the worlds of truth through all the 
channels of knowledge ; but he contends that the 
division, instead of being in consequence discredited, 
is only thereby proved to be in conformity with the 
inclusive nature of dialectics. Surely it proves 
rather that a dialectic thus inclusive is incompetent 
to draw specific distinctions. It would, besides, be 
difficult, if not impossible, to make out, as regards 
the particular sciences, even the predominance or 
preponderance asserted. Other objections suggest 
themselves, but may be withheld. 

The work of Prof. Conti, U Vero nelV Oi'dine ContL 
(2 vols., 1876), is very largely occupied with the 
doctrine of the sciences. The encyclopaedic problem 
is the theme of the eleventh chapter. Science, 
history, and art are represented as the departments 
of human knowledge. Science is the first in the 
order of reflection, but the last in the order 
of formation. It is to be divided into Philo- 
sophy, Mathematics, Physics, and Positive Theology. 
Philosophy is either speculative or practical, in the 



250 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 



former case including Ontology, Rational Theology, 
Cosmology, and Psychology; in the latter Logic, 
^Esthetics, and Ethics. Mathematics is either p 
or a Physics comprehends Physics in the 

special sense of the term, Chemistry, Physiology, 
and Pathology, and Physical Anthropology. Posi- 
tive Theology is founded upon authority, and 
therefore to be entirely separated from the theology 
which, being based on reason, is a part of philosophy. 
I leave it to the reader to criticise that scheme for 
himself. 



&Erd- In 1877 an article of Benno Erdmann on the 

"Gliederung der Wissenschaften " appeared in the 
Vierteljahrschrif't fur uismisehctftliche Phihsoj 
Bd. iL, Hft. L It is marked by the clearness and 
penetration characteristic of its author, and although 
in its general conclusions there may be little that is 
remarkable, the observations which it contains on 
the nature and limits of various particular sciences 
are undoubtedly most worthy of consideration. The 
aciences as a whole are conceived of by Erdmann as 
a system conversant with a complex of regular series 
of elementary data. Each series is represented by 
a special discipline, and there are as many groups of 
sciences as there are different kinds of series. The 
mathematical sciences constitute the first great 
group, as their series are resolvable into absolutely 






FROM BAIN TO WUNDT. 251 

like elements and purely logical relations. The sci- 
ences concerned with causal connection and real 
evolution are, then, divided into formal — those 
which seek general laws — and material or historical 
— those which deal with the processes of change 
which arise from the interaction of general laws. It 
is next argued that in the present state of our know- 
ledge we must also distribute them into mechan- 
ical and psychical — Naturwissenschaften and 
Geisteswisserischaften — but with the admission that 
this distinction may eventually be discovered to be 
unwarranted. After a few general remarks on the 
formal mechanical sciences, the historico- mechan- 
ical sciences — Astronomy, Geology, Anorganology, 
Organology, Anthropology — are more fully char- 
acterised. The sciences held to belong at once to 
the formal and the psychical class are Psychology 
and the normative sciences of knowing (Logic and 
Theory of Cognition), of willing in conduct toward 
things (Ethic), and of feeling in the appreciation 
of things (^Esthetic). While Psychology treats of 
psychical processes as they are, the other psychical 
sciences just mentioned discuss their validity. The 
historico -psychical sciences are unfortunately not 
described and distributed. The sciences even when 
combined are, according to Erdmann, incomplete ; 
between them and within them there are blanks 
or gaps which can only be filled up in a hypo- 



252 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

thetical manner; and there is a discipline — not 
entitled to be called a science — which has this 
function — namely, Metaphysics. Besides may be 
appended Psedagogy and Theology, the former an 
art based on Psychology and Ethics, and the latter 
one which undertakes to satisfy the interest of the 
general understanding in the ultimate questions of 
knowledge in a way conducive to culture and 
progress. 

These are the findings of Dr Benno Erdmann. 
Some of them are, I think, not in the least made 
out. A little reflection on the distinctive nature 
of Theology, on the character of its relation to 
the sciences, and on the number of disciplines, 
some of which are plainly theoretical, which it 
embraces, should suffice to show that it cannot 
properly be ranked along with Paedagogy, and 
regarded as merely a practical appendage to 
psychical research and metaphysical conjecture. 
The account given of the function of Metaphysics 
is more amusing than edifying. If true, she who 
was erewhile held to be the queen of the sciences 
is, in reality, but a degraded and untrustworthy 
handmaiden who mends their tattered garments 
by patching them with cobwebs. It is obviously, 
however, not true, for the whole representation given 
of Metaphysics is but a mutilated and caricatured 
reflection of the idea of a doctrine of the sciences — 



FROM BAIN TO WUNDT. 253 

a doctrine which has for aim to trace the limits, 
note the defects, and exhibit the relations of the 
sciences, as much without hypothesis or conjecture 
as possible. In regard to the so-called normative 
psychical sciences due weight is not assigned to the 
fact that the validity of the distinctions between 
truth and error, right and wrong, beauty and 
deformity, can no more be shown to result from 
mental than from mechanical processes, and must 
be the object of investigations of a kind commonly 
called metaphysical. 

Prof. Simone Corleo has treated of the doctrine of Corieo. 
the sciences, or, as he calls it, Sophology, in his 
Sistema delta Filosqfia Universale (Rome, 1880). 
He distributes the sciences into physical, meta- 
physical, and moral, and gives under each head an 
ample enumeration of particular disciplines ; but he 
does not show how his classes are related, or group 
their constituent members, or arrange these mem- 
bers in their natural order of sequence, contiguity, 
or dependence. The classification is the conclusion 
of his work. It is preceded by a special treatment 
of psychology, anthropology, and sociology. The 
treatise as a whole is a very acute and ingenious 
exposition of a philosophy of identity. The author 
has earnestly and skilfully combated atheism, pan- 
theism, and other inadequate representations of 
the Divine. His name has an honourable place 



254 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

among Italian patriots in a great crisis of Italian 
history. 

Bourdeau. M. L. Bourdeau, in his elaborate Thtorie des 
sciences (2 vols., 1882), resumed the work of Comte 
in the spirit of Comte, seeking to expound an 
"integral" or universal science into which shall 
enter no metaphysical or theological conception. 
His treatise is one of very great importance, to 
which, were the publication of my studies on the 
scientia scientiarum continued, I should have 
frequently to refer. At present, however, I need 
only state that, like Comte, he arranges what he 
regards as fundamental sciences in a single linear 
series ; and that series runs as follows : 1. Positive 
Ontology or Logic, the science of realities, employ- 
ing the method of intuition ; 2. Metrology or Mathe- 
matics, the science of magnitudes, employing the 
method of deduction; 3. Theseology or Dynamics, 
the science of positions, employing the method of 
observation ; 4. Poiology or Physics, the science of 
modalities, employing the method of experimenta- 
tion ; 5. Craseology or Chemistry, the science of 
combinations, employing the method of integration ; 
6. Morphology, the science of forms, employing the 
method of comparison; and 7. Praxeology, the 
science of functions, employing the method of 
connection. The Ontology of M. Bourdeau is 



PROM BAIN TO WUNDT. 255 

mainly a kind of Psychology, and not entitled, it 
seems to me, to the place of priority which he 
assigns it. At least one whole department of his 
Theseology — that of Kinetics — properly belongs to 
Mathematics. The way in which he distinguishes 
Morphology and Praxeology, and divides and dis- 
tributes both, is the most original and ingenious 
part of his scheme, and I regret that I cannot give 
it the consideration which it merits. I think it 
could be shown that the separation of forms and 
functions, necessary and important although it be 
within certain limits, is not so radical and far- 
reaching as he would make it. The new designa- 
tions which he gives to the methods of the sciences 
seem as little to be, commended as the new names 
which he applies to the sciences themselves. Of 
course, the objections which hold good against 
positivism in general must hold good against the 
positivism of M. Bourdeau. 

The Order of the Sciences, an Essay on the Shields. 
Philosophical Classification and Organisation of 
Human Knowledge, published in 1882 by Prof. 
Charles W. Shields, of Princeton, may fairly be 
ranked among the best of the smaller treatises which 
have appeared on the subject of which it treats. 
Its exhibition of the scheme of scientific distribution 
adopted is clear and skilful; its criticism of other 



256 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

classifications is discriminating and incisive. The 
author successively enunciates and applies to his 
problem the following principles : "1. A phil- 
osophical scheme of the sciences should be based 
upon the facts which support them, rather than 
upon the ideas which they involve; 2. Such a 
scheme should fully reflect all the distinct classes 
of facts which have been scientifically ascertained ; 
3. It should exhibit all classes of facts in their 
actual connections as coexistent in space and 
successive in time ; 4. It should embrace both the 
empirical and metaphysical divisions of the sciences 
in logical correlation ; and 5. It should have its 
completion in a general science of all the other 
sciences, based upon their historical and logical 
evolution." 

A strict application of the first of these prin- 
ciples, he thinks, " would exclude the abstract 
sciences of Logic and Mathematics from a phil- 
osophical classification, and retain them as dis- 
ciplinal studies, until, by being employed in 
empirical investigations, they acquire a content 
of positive knowledge, when they simply become 
parts and processes of other more real sciences." 
As regards the second principle, he holds "that 
the progress of science has brought into view six 
distinct classes of facts, affording ground for as 
many corresponding groups of fundamental sciences 



FROM BAIN TO WUNDT. 257 

— the Physical, the Chemical, the Organical, the 
Psychical, the Social, and the Religious." In con- 
nection with his third principle he maintains that, 
"although the different classes of facts are distinct 
and separate, yet they are found succeeding one 
another in a fixed order of mutual dependence 
and increasing multiformity, each involving its 
predecessor, and becoming a condition precedent 
to its successor; and with such actual procession 
of phenomena must correspond the normal pro- 
cession of the sciences." He also lays down a 
series of what he calls Principal Sciences — Astron- 
omy, Geology, Anthropology, Psychology, Soci- 
ology, and Theology — "each Principal Science 
representing, in a concrete form, the parallel group 
of Fundamental Sciences to which it corresponds, 
and including, as its special domain, all of those 
Fundamental Sciences from which it is not excluded 
by its immediate predecessor and successor in the 
series." All these sciences, he argues, exemplify 
the fourth principle by being half empirical and 
half metaphysical. And he concludes by treating 
of the conditions and nature of that terminal science 
which, as the fifth proposition affirms, must organise 
and complete all other sciences. 

In the following respects these views of Dr 
Shields fail to command my assent. The ideas 
of a science may be its facts, as, for example, in 

R 



258 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

Mathematics, which is truly science in its most 
perfect form and no merely disciplinal study. 
Further, ideas may give to the facts their distinc- 
tive character. Only if the idea of God have 
validity can religious facts be more than simply 
facts of psychology. But for the idea which under- 
lies it theology would have to be included in 
mental pathology. Again, moral and aesthetic 
facts seem as distinct from merely psychical facts 
as social and religious facts. Then, I cannot 
concur in the acceptance of Comte's doctrine of 
a single linear series of sciences. The relationship 
of the sciences is not truly represented when it is 
reduced to a Bimple order of sequence. The con- 
ception of a series of Principal Sciences parallel 
to a series of Fundamental Sciences also appears 
very questionable. Is it not misleading, for in- 
stance, to bring together Astronomy and Theology 
as Principal Sciences, seeing that Astronomy is 
merely one of a number of sciences of physical 
facts, whereas Theology is the science of religious 
facts? Further, while holding that the sciences 
involve metaphysical ideas or conditions, I do not 
deem it correct to maintain that they have each 
a metaphysical part. To do so ignores the con- 
nection of the categories, and is inconsistent 
with the unity and independence of metaphysics. 
Finally, while accepting Dr Shields's account of the 



FROM BAIN TO WUNDT. 259 

function of the doctrine of science as thoroughly 
just, I cannot regard the doctrine itself as the 
terminal science, but only as the first department 
of philosophy. 

Mr H. M. Stanley, another American writer Stanley, 
favourably known by his contributions to philo- 
sophy and mental science, has published a paper, 
well worthy of consideration, On the Classification 
of the Sciences, in Mind, No. XXXIV., April 1884. 
It is necessary to leave unnoticed his remarks on 
the historical classification of the sciences, as also 
on the distinction between Static and Dynamic 
Sciences, and to state only the general result at 
which he arrives as to a logical classification. He 
places Mathematics alongside of all other sciences, 
"not as constitutive, but as concomitant"; and 
then gives the following series of the sciences, as 
one which is determined by " the principle of aggre- 
gation " : 1. Chemistry — the Science of Atom ; 2. 
Molecular Physics — Science of Molecule; 3. Molar 
Physics — Science of Mass; 4. Biology — Science of 
Aggregated Cell-Masses ; 5. Psychology — Science of 
Individual Man ; 6. Sociology — Science of Human 
Aggregates; and 7. Theology — Science of God. 
" The order of aggregation," he says, " plainly is : 
Atoms into molecules, molecules into masses, cell- 
masses into plants, animals, and men, and these 



260 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

into societies. Nature is thus a combination of 
wheels within wheels. This classification presents 
the general order of the dependence of the sciences. 
If we wish, for instance, to study in Sociology the 
family, there will be necessarily presupposed a know- 
ledge of the human individual as a psychical whole ; 
and this presupposes a study of the human animal, 
and this of the cell, and this of masses, molecules, 
and atoms. Herein is a * hierarchy of the sciences.' 
If this be the order of dependence of the sciences, 
it must also be the order of their completion, the 
higher sciences necessarily waiting on the lower. 
Again, it is also the order of increasing complexity, 
as has been exemplified throughout. It is also 
the order of increasing speciality and concreteness, 
in that it is a logical order of increasing intension 
and decreasing extension. A number of objects 
decrease, and numbers of attributes increase. It 
is also the order of recognised rank." 

On this simple yet ingenious scheme of Mr 
Stanley the following criticisms may be offered : 
First, it is not shown that Mathematics only is so 
concomitant with the other sciences that it cannot 
be simply placed in a series of the sciences. The 
same is true of Logic, inasmuch as all other sciences 
are built up by logical processes. The same is true 
even of Theology, inasmuch as all other sciences 
furnish materials for Theology. Secondly, the con- 



PROM BAIN TO WUNDT. 261 

ception given of the nature and position of Chem- 
istry seems untenable. Chemistry is defined as the 
Science of the Atom, and as such is regarded as the 
first constitutive science. In reality, Chemistry has 
not yet proved the existence of the atom. The 
atom is still only an assumption, and may turn out 
to be a pseudo-metaphysical fiction. And should 
its existence be scientifically established, it is most 
improbable that it will not be found to have 
properties and relations of a mechanical order, 
simpler and more general than its chemical charac- 
teristics. Chemistry has not to do with atoms more 
than with molecules and masses. It has to do with 
the analysis of compounds into elements and the 
synthesis of elements into compounds. It is, as 
M. Bourdeau says, the science of combinations. 
Thirdly, the principle of aggregation is insufficient 
and unsuited for the classification of the sciences. 
It is just because there are distinctions of things 
which cannot be explained by aggregation that 
there are distinct sciences. If life and mind could 
be shown to be simply aggregates, Biology and 
Psychology would be at the same time resolved 
into Chemistry. Sociology can have no claim to 
be more than a department of Psychology unless it 
can be shown to be more than "human aggrega- 
tion." The idea of God, in which Theology is 
rooted, is not that of an aggregate. 



262 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

d. o. Mr Daniel Greenleaf Thompson, also an American, 

exhibits a tabular scheme of classification of the 
Sciences in his System of Psychology (vol. i. p. 
76, 7), published in 1884. His main division is into 
(a) Sciences relating primarily to the extended — 
Non-Ego Sciences; and (b) Sciences relating prim- 
arily to the unextended — Ego Sciences. Class A is 
subdivided into Physics and Biology, each of which 
is represented as including various Abstract and 
Concrete Sciences. Class B is subdivided into Theor- 
etical and Practical Sciences. The former are sub- 
divided into : 1. Sciences of Mind in its relations to 
itself, comprehending the Abstract Sciences of Logic, 
Mathematics, and ^Esthetics, and the Concrete 
Sciences of Psychology and Ethnology; and 2. 
Sciences of Mind in its relation to other Minds, 
comprehending the Science of Human Communica- 
tion and Sociology, with its related group of studies. 
The scheme, it may be perceived, is of an external 
and artificial kind. It rests on no principle, pro- 
ceeds on no consistent method, and is pervaded by no 
general philosophical conception. It counts various 
sciences twice, first as theoretical and next as prac- 
tical, and it is not apparent why all are not so 
dealt with, while it seems almost absurd to confine 
the distinction of Theoretical and Practical to the 
Ego-Sciences. Mathematics and Logic are placed 
after all the physical sciences, although both are 



PROM BAIN TO WUNDT. 263 

plainly presupposed by all these sciences. While 
prominence is given to the questionable distinc- 
tion of Abstract and Concrete Sciences, the much 
more significant one of Fundamental and Deriv- 
ative Sciences is ignored. No room is found for 
Theology. Several other errors of Bain and Spencer 
are reproduced. 

It is now necessary to give some account of the De 
views of M. E. De Roberty on the subject in hand. 
He is a native of Russia but lives in Paris, and is a 
most industrious as well as very able French publi- 
cist. He is a thorough positivist, but very far from 
a mere Comtist or, indeed, a mere disciple of any 
teacher. He often rejects Comte's conclusions and 
substitutes for them very different views of his own ; 
and, in fact, is one of the most independent as well 
as one of the most interesting and instructive con- 
temporary thinkers of the positivist school. Of all 
criticisms of Comte and contributions to positivism 
those of Roberty are, perhaps, on the whole, the 
most thorough and suggestive. 

His views on the classification of the sciences are 
to be found chiefly in his La Sociologies 1881. 
There he has distributed all that he regards as 
sciences into four groups. The reason given for 
doing so is that the sciences of each of those groups 
rest on different ways of observation. The sciences 



264 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

of the first group are held by him to be the mathe- 
matical sciences, on the ground that they rest on 
simple intuitions or self- evident axioms. Astron- 
omy, on the other hand, is made to do duty as 
representative of a second kind of science, or perhaps 
group of sciences, because based on pure and simple 
observation. Physics and Chemistry are adduced 
as constitutive of a third class, and one of special 
interest inasmuch as dependent not only on observa- 
tion but on observation conjoined with experiment- 
ation. And, further, there is a fourth class, the 
sciences of which are designated by Roberty de- 
scriptive sciences, because grounded on what he 
calls scientific description, — a process on which he 
has dealt at considerable length and to which he 
attaches great importance. In that last class he has 
included Mechanics, Biology, Psychology, and Soci- 
ology. To Sociology he assigns the same place, 
and attributes much of the same importance, as 
Comte had done. The definitive co-ordination of 
the sciences he holds to be the task to which the 
Philosophy of the Sciences is bound to devote 
itself, — a task which is still in the future but will 
not fail to be accomplished. Six years later than 
La Sociologie appeared his L'Aneienne et la Nouvelle 
Philosophic (1887), which was followed by five 
works, the parts of a single system of thought, and 
the titles of which are L'Inconnaissable (1889), 



FROM BAIN TO WUNDT. 265 

La Philosophic du Steele (1891), Agnosticisme 
(1892), La Recherche de Funiti (1893), and Auguste 
Comte et Herbert Spencer (1894). They are all 
meant to be contributions to a true philosophy of 
the sciences, a scientia scientiarum, a whole of 
positive sciences alone, one on which each positive 
science depends for its development on the ante- 
cedent sciences, and on which all real philosophy 
depends exclusively on all real positive sciences. 
They are all meant also to convince their readers 
that " the whole of religion and the whole of phil- 
osophy so-called " have nothing in them of the real 
nature of science; that there is no such thing as 
theological or metaphysical science; that even the 
so-called criticism of Kant, the positivist agnosti- 
cism of Comte, the conditioned or relativist agnos- 
ticism of Hamilton and Mansel, and the evolutionist 
agnosticism of Spencer are all forms of pseudo- 
science or of philosophy falsely so called. 

The courage and self-consistency of Roberty in 
extruding all theology and metaphysics from what 
he considers knowledge or science, and his per- 
spicacity in showing that very much of what has 
been affirmed by modern Agnostics is as non- 
sensical as anything of an analogous kind which 
can be laid to the charge of medieval scholastics, 
are worthy of recognition, but he has quite failed 
to prove all metaphysics and theology to be of 



266 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

an agnostic, unscientific, or anti - scientific char- 
acter. Rightly understood, both metaphysics and 
theology may be sciences. The exclusion of all 
theology and metaphysics, of all religion and 
philosophy, from the rank and nature of 
sciences, is a serious defect in a classification 
of the sciences. The views of Roberty and 
others to the contrary are somewhat fully dealt 
with in my Croall Lectures on Agnosticism for 
1887-88. Roberty's first group of sciences are 
the mathematical. Some of those sciences, how- 
ever, are among the latest, and, alike on historical 
and rational grounds, it may be questioned whether 
any of them were the earliest. Logic, for example, 
may perhaps have preceded any of them both in 
India and Greece. It is somewhat difficult to 
conceive how mathematics could have arisen until 
preceded by a considerable knowledge of know- 
ledge, a clear apprehension of the axioms on which 
mathematics rest, and of the rules and processes 
of reasoning. Scientific knowledge has in almost 
all departments so grown out of ordinary know- 
ledge that it is difficult to determine where the 
latter has ended and the former begun. Further, 
Roberty describes astronomy as representative of 
a second group of sciences on the ground that 
it is a science of 'pure and simple observation. 
But is it so ? What would have become of 



FROM BAIN TO WUNDT. 267 

astronomy were it confined to observation and 
left unaided by calculation? Other questions are 
suggested by Roberty's classification. My readers 
may raise and answer them for themselves. His 
scheme is a meagre one compared with many 
others that I have already noticed. That does 
not, however, much affect the value of his 
writings, which I wish were more widely known 
in Britain. 

The name of Wm. Wundt is much more widely Wundt. 
known than that of De Roberty. Although born 
in 1832, Wundt is still an indefatigable teacher 
and experimentalist. Physiology has doubtless 
been the main subject of his studies, seeing that 
as privat - docent and professor he has publicly 
taught it for the long period of forty -seven 
years, but he has also by original investigations 
left his mark on many of the chief sciences. 
Even on logic, ethics, and psychology he has 
written most elaborate and very valuable 
treatises. It is only natural, therefore, that he 
should have occupied himself earnestly with the 
problem of the relations of the sciences to one 
another. His range of knowledge must be greatly 
wider and more exact than was that of Comte. 
If less of a philosopher than was Spencer, he is 
much more of a scientist. The works in which 



268 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

he has treated of the classification of the sciences 
are his Logik, Bd. ii. (1883), his Philosophische 
Studien, Bd. v. Th. 1 (1886), and his System 
der Philosophie (1889). They show that he has 
thoroughly realised the importance of classification 
of the sciences, and of the dependence of the 
sciences on philosophy. 

Perhaps it is in the last of the works men- 
tioned that he has most completely expounded 
and defended his conception of philosophy as 'a 
science of all the positive sciences/ as ' the uni- 
versal science which has to do with the cogni- 
tions obtained by the particular sciences into a 
consistent system/ His Logic is described by 
himself as 'an investigation of the principles of 
knowledge and of the methods of scientific re- 
search/ Hence its first volume is expressly de- 
signated an Erhentnislehre and the second a 
Methodenlehre, — the former being regarded as the 
general theory of logic or of real and formal in- 
vestigation and reasoning, and the latter as a study 
of the principles, methods, and acquisitions of the 
special sciences. In the second edition of 1895 
the Methodenlehre was greatly enlarged and elabor- 
ated so as to be much superior to any corresponding 
chapters in J. S. Mill's Logic. The volume con- 
sists of four main sections with subdivisions. It 
begins with 'a general doctrine of method* (pp. 



FROM BAIN TO WUNDT. 269 

1-73), and then expounds the logic of mathematics, 
treating first of its method so far as general, and 
then in the following order of succession the special 
methods of arithmetic, geometry, functions, and 
infinitesimals (pp. 74-219). The logic of the natural 
sciences is similarly dealt with : an exposition of 
the general foundation of natural investigation 
being first given, and then in due order an ex- 
position of the special logical methods of physics, 
chemistry, physiology, and biology. The logic of 
the mental sciences is dealt with in the same 
manner. The bases common to them all are first 
laid bare, and then those of the historical and 
social sciences are specially described. The volume 
is brought to a close with an elaborate exposition 
of the methods of philosophy (pp. 478-620). 

As already said, Wundt has also dealt with the 
classification of the sciences in his Philosophische 
Studien, Bd. v. Th. 1, 1886. There he divides 
the general system of the sciences into I. Par- 
ticular Sciences, and II. Philosophy, and subdivides 
both. I. The Particular Sciences he distributes 
into two great groups — Formal Sciences and Real- 
istic Sciences. (A) Formal sciences are the mathe- 
matical sciences, and of these a detailed enumera- 
tion and description are given. (B) Realistic 
sciences are subdivided into two sections — viz., 
(a) Physical sciences and (b) Mental sciences. The 



270 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

latter are subdivided thus : — (a) Theory of the 
phenomena of spirit (i.e., psychology under its 
different forms) : (6) Sciences of the products of 
spirit (philology and social sciences) ; and (c) 
Science of the development of the products of the 
spirit (history under its different forms). II. Philo- 
sophy itself is thus subdivided: — (a) Theory of 
knowledge (both formal and realistic) ; and (6) 
Theory of principles, which under its general form 
is metaphysics and under its particular forms is 
philosophy of nature and philosophy of spirit. 

A still later attempt of Wundt's at the distribu- 
tion of the sciences is to be found in his System 
der Philosophie (1889). The view of it given by 
Prof. Ladd of Yale in his Introduction to Philo- 
sophy (1891) is so brief, exact, and accurate, and 
so likely to be better than any I could myself 
produce, that I shall venture to avail myself of it. 

The most recent important work aiming at a system of 
philosophy is by Wundt. As might be expected from its 
author, this treatise on synthetic philosophy is everywhere 
conceived and executed in a spirit of fidelity to the method 
and results of the particular sciences. Wundt regards 
philosophy as a universal science, having for its problem 
to unite the cognitions of the particular sciences into a 
consistent system. On account of the relation in which 
it stands to these sciences, its divisions must be based on 
the division of the sciences. Two main problems are, 
therefore, given to philosophy in its efforts to treat syn- 



FROM BAIN TO WUNDT. 



271 



thetically all the particular sciences. The first of these 
problems relates to knowing in a process of becoming; 
the second, to knowing already become ( Wissen, Werdende, 
and Qevnrdene). Hence the two main divisions of philo- 
sophy are (1) Science of Cognition, (2) Science of Prin- 
ciples. These two divisions are then developed into a 
scheme, which may be tabulated as follows: — 

Division of Scientific Philosophy. 



I. Science of 
knowledge. 



II. Science of 
Principles. 



2. Real. 



1. General, or 
Metaphy sic, 



2. Special. 



:f 



f 1. Formal (Formal Logic). 

A. History of Knowledge. 

B. Theory of Knowledge, which in con- 
nection with formal logic constitutes 
Logic in the wider meaning of the word, 
is then further subdivided into— 

(a) General Theory of knowledge. 
(6) Theory of Special Methods as 
applied to scientific investigation. 
The systematic exposition of the funda- 
mental conceptions, and fundamental 
laws of all science. 

A. Philosophy of Nature, which is Bub- 
divided into — 

(a) General Cosmology, and (6) Gen- 
eral Biology. 

B. Philosophy of Spirit, which has three 
subdivisions — 

(a) Ethics, (6) ^Esthetics, and (c) 
Philosophy of Religion. 



On the foundation of the three divisions of the Philosophy 
of Spirit, and with the help of a comprehensive survey of 
human development, stands the Philosophy of History. 
Its aim is to give a picture of the whole external and 
internal life of man. 1 

Wundt's classification of the sciences merits, I 
have no doubt, a fuller exposition of it than has just 



Ladd, pp. 167, 168. 



272 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

been given. A criticism of it I shall not undertake, 
although on several points it seems to be not beyond 
criticism. The scheme has, I think, a considerable 
number of defects. Its merits seem far from equal 
to those of the work done by the author of it on the 
methodology of the sciences included in it. It is on 
the latter, not on the former, that Prof. Wundt's 
labours are of such very exceptional value. Only 
experts, and experts of an extraordinary range of 
knowledge, can be expected fully to appreciate how 
great those merits are. As a general review of 
Wundt's conclusions as to the classification, logic, 
and system of the sciences I know none better 
than Prof. Venn's in Mind, vol. ix. pp. 451-468. 
To it I refer my readers. 



VH. FROM MASARYK TO KARL PEARSON. 

Maaaryk. T. G. Masaryk, professor in the University of 
Prague, in 1866 published in the Bohemian language 
a book on " the classification and organisation of the 
sciences." Fortunately a German translation ap- 
peared in the following year. It would well deserve 
translation also into other European languages, as 
there is scarcely any other work so likely to serve 
well as an introduction to as many sciences ; for, 
although its author modestly acknowledges that only 



FROM MASARYK TO KARL PEARSON. 273 

on some sociological and psychological departments 
of research can he make any claim to write as an 
expert, he has obviously made a thoughtful general 
study of most of the principal sciences, and acquired 
an adequate acquaintance with the literature regard- 
ing them. The authorities on which he relies are of 
a good kind. With British philosophical literature 
he is exceptionally well acquainted. The English 
authors to whom he refers most frequently are 
Bacon, Bain, Faraday, Rowan Hamilton, Sir Win. 
Hamilton, Hume, Locke, J. S. Mill, Newton, 
H. Spencer, and Whewell ; the French, DesCartes, 
A. Comte, Pascal, and Roberty; and the German, 
Du Bois-Reymond, Dilthey, Fechner, Harms, Kant, 
Leibniz, and Wundt. That Italian authors are so 
much overlooked is to be regretted. 

The German title of Masaryk's treatise is Versuch 
einer Concreten Logik, and his introductory remarks 
are clear and relevant as to the need of a classifica- 
tion and also an organisation of the sciences. With 
regard to the character of classification, while affirm- 
ing its necessity, he allows that there is something 
artificial in every classification, and that neither 
evidence, certainty, nor method can be its sufficient 
principle. The order and relationships of the 
sciences ought to be determined by the nature of 
their objects. Theoretical and practical sciences, 
however, are to be separated. There is the widest 

s 



274 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

distance between them. Abstract and concrete 
sciences are less so, both classes being theoretical 
sciences. All these sciences — abstract and concrete 
alike — are occupied with the natures of certain kinds 
of objects, the systems of truth that may be elicited 
from special spheres of knowledge. What the so- 
called practical sciences aim at is the attainment 
of desired ends, the accomplishment of purposes 
deemed useful. All sciences may be applied to 
several uses, and all arts may be more or less related 
to some science or sciences. To enclose them in the 
same scheme cannot be rightly effected, but merely 
made to seem so, by a cross and confusing division. 
The study of the sciences is one thing, the applica- 
tion of them to ends and identification of them 
with arts another. Masaryk's so-called * practical 
sciences' seem to have been counted by him as 
both seven and twelve. There might, I think, 
have been many more. His list of them is as 
follows : A. Calculation and Measurement. De- 
scriptive Geometry. Theory of industrial and 
imitative Arts; B. Technology in widest sense 
(Kendering serviceable the forces of nature); C. 
Physical and curative education (Phytotechnic, 
Zootechnic, Medicine, and Hygiene) ; D. Training 
of the character and understanding (Pedagogic and 
Didactic), Politics, and Ethics (as science of the 



FROM MASARYK TO KARL PEARSON. 275 

complete guidance of life) ; E. Practical Grammar 
(Mastery of Language) ; F. Practical ^Esthetic ; and 
G. Practical Logic. Such is Masaryk's enumeration 
of so-called * practical sciences/ 

Obviously some of them would have been better 
placed among arts, while others are as properly 
sciences and should have been so designated. 
Sciences and arts may be intimately connected, 
but to call either arts sciences or sciences arts is 
an error, and must lead to confusion as it has 
obviously done in Masaryk's scheme. That scheme 
owes more to Comte than to any one else, and 
indeed so much that the author of it may be 
fairly regarded as a Comtist, a very independent 
and sagacious one however, who cannot be reason- 
ably charged with having taken the views of 
Comte, or any one else, without close and careful 
consideration. He has rejected even Comte's 
linear series of the sciences and substituted for it 
a binary classification, although his own classifica- 
tion thereby loses the sort of unity which per- 
vades Comte's scheme, and to which more than 
anything else that scheme has owed its popularity. 
But for its simplicity Comte's classification would 
never have been preferred to a considerable 
number of the more complex schemes that have 
been already described in our pages. 



276 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

As already stated, Masaryk distributes his 
c theoretical sciences ' into ' abstract sciences ' and 
'concrete sciences/ There has been much con- 
troversy as to what should be meant by the terms 
'abstract/ 'concrete/ and also 'abstract- concrete/ 
Comte, Littre, Spencer, and others have been 
engaged in it without arriving at any very definite 
or important result. There is no mere abstractness 
or mere concreteness in the objects of any of the 
sciences. The term abstract-concrete should imply 
that and neither more nor less. The division or 
classification of sciences into abstract and concrete 
cannot be a complete division, a perfect classifica- 
tion. It may, however, be none the less but all 
the more instructive on that account, as showing 
how intimately all sciences are related. Pro! 
Masaryk attaches great importance to Comte's 
doctrine of a hierarchy of sciences, — a closely 
connected series of fundamental sciences. Sub- 
stantially he adopts it as a whole, yet obviously 
after a close and independent study of it. Hence 
he is often accurate where Comte was not, and 
brings to light what Comte had left in darkness. 
All the sciences of the hierarchy are, of course, 
represented by him as abstract sciences, — not 
concrete and still less so-called practical sciences. 
Hence it is now necessary to indicate what in his 
scheme of classification are the abstract sciences and 



FROM MASARYK TO KARL PEARSON. 277 

especially what are the sciences of the hierarchy. 
The following table may suffice : — 

The Theoretical Abstract Sciences. 

A. The Sciences of the Hierarchy (Fundamental 
Sciences). The idea of a hierarchy of the sciences 
was first clearly set forth in the Pansophiw 
Diatyposis (1645) of Comenius. 

I. Mathematics. — To it is assigned by Masaryk 
precedence in the hierarchical sciences and con- 
sequently of all other sciences. His description 
and distribution of the mathematical sciences seem 
to be about as accurate as could possibly be given 
in fifteen pages (71-86) by one professedly not a 
mathematical expert; and show how carefully he 
has utilised not only the well-known works of 
Comte, Bain, and Wundt so far as they bear on 
the subject, but also such works as Baumann's 
Lehren von Raum, Zeit und Mathematik in der 
neuesten Philosophic, Clifford's Common Sense of 
the Exact Sciences, Cantor's Vorlesungen iiber 
Geschichte der Mathematik, De Morgan On the 
Study and Difficulties of Mathematics, Duhamel's 
Des Mithodes dans les sciences de raisonnement, 
Kroman's Beitrdge zu einer Theorie der Mathe- 
matik und Physik, and Schmitz - Dumont's Die 
mathematischen Elemente der Erkenntnisstheorie. 
Mathematics is, however, a very comprehensive 



278 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

term. It is the name not merely of a science 
but of a system of sciences, and these closely 
interrelated sciences, each of which rests on a 
fundamental idea or ideas, and has a corre- 
spondency different method. Space, magnitude, 
figure, number, time, motion, direction, rate, limit, 
&c, are all foundations of mathematical reasoning, 
and all mathematical sciences have so far their 
own distinctive methods. Arithmetic and Geo- 
metry are very different both as to matter and 
method from the Calculus and Kinematics. That 
is not sufficiently indicated by Masaryk. He has, 
however, clearly stated the advantages which the 
mathematical sciences have in important respects 
over all other sciences, and also their limitations. 
II. Mechanics. — According to Masaryk it is the 
second hierarchical science ; one which has very 
much in common with, and is to a great extent 
dependent on, Mathematics. It has even been 
often included among the mathematical sciences. 
Mach in a treatise on 'the development of 
mechanics * has contested its right to be so placed, 
and Masaryk deems his argumentation probably 
conclusive. Perhaps he is right in thinking so, 
but certainly Mechanics is both abstract and con- 
crete, both quantitative and qualitative, and cannot 
be denied to be on the borderland between mathe- 
matical and physical science, and to lie almost as 



FROM MASARYK TO KARL PEARSON. 279 

much within the territory of the one as of the 
other. 

III. Physics. — That third so-called hierarchical 
science is comprehensive of a large class of sciences, 
namely, all those which deal with inorganic physical 
things, or, in other words, with the properties and 
changes of matter in their molecular constitution, 
and therefore with hardness, elasticity, cohesion, 
&c, as also with heat, light, sound, electricity, 
magnetism, &c. All the sciences referred to are 
occupied with these objects, their properties, and 
effects. They are all inductive sciences and de- 
pendent on observation and experimentation. 
Masaryk declines to arrange the departmental 
physical sciences in any serial order. He regards 
Comte's attempt to do so as a failure. 

IV. Chemistry. — It seems strange that Chemistry 
should not have been included among physical 
sciences but ranked as an hierarchical science. In 
its present condition even it seems closely akin to 
and dependent on the physical sciences, and appears 
likely to be much more so in the future. What 
separates Chemistry from Physics as described by 
Masaryk is that while physical processes leave the 
material structure of things ordinarily unchanged, 
chemical processes leave a profound and lasting 
change. In other words, what is distinctive of 
Chemistry as compared with Physics is what is 



280 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

called * chemical affinity/ a peculiar and as yet 
altogether mysterious ability of matter to enter in 
its smallest parts into an intimate connection of a 
kind confined to Chemistry alone. Its products are 
completely new. No other science apparently takes 
us so deeply into the nature of matter. A complete 
knowledge of the evolution of molecules may go far 
to explain the evolution of worlds. The infinitely 
little may be a key to acquaintance with the in- 
finitely great. Experimentation has a large place 
in Chemistry. What measuring is in Geometry, 
weighing may not unreasonably be said, as it is by 
Masaryk, to be in Chemistry. 

V. Biology. — To this fifth hierarchical science in 
Masaryk's scheme both Physics and Chemistry are 
represented by him as subservient, while holding 
great injury to have been done to it by a crude 
materialism in unreasonable attempts to explain life 
and its operations by inadequate causes. A com- 
pletely satisfactory method of studying it is held 
to have been as yet far from adequately ascertained. 
Mere conjectures and conflicting hypotheses abound in 
it. Its province is an extremely wide one, including 
not merely a single science but many sciences, as, e.g., 
Anatomy and Physiology, Botany and Zoology, &c. 

VI. Psychology. — It is closely connected with and 
largely dependent on Biology. Life is presupposed 
in every psychological process. That life has origin- 



FROM MASARTK TO KARL PEARSON. 281 

ated out of mere matter (if there be such a thing), 
has not been fully proved, but no one doubts that 
where there is no vitality there can be no mental 
states. Thought, feeling, and volition in every 
form, all phases and stages of consciousness, pre- 
suppose life, not death. Of all the mental sciences 
Psychology is the fundamental science — the Grund- 
wissenschaft. Masaryk's treatment of it (in pp. 116- 
138) seems to be very judicious. 

VII. Sociology. — Like other positivists, Masaryk 
regards Sociology as the crowning hierarchical 
science, and naturally deals with it at much more 
length than with any preceding science. He adopts 
Comte's division of it into Social Statics and Social 
Dynamics, and also distributes its contents into 
Theoretical and Practical Sociology. Its connec- 
tions with, and bearings on, other sciences are like- 
wise traced, and the history as well as probable results 
of its development and findings are referred to. Biol- 
ogy, Psychology, and Sociology are the inseparable 
stages in a vast and complex system of evolution. 

B. Outside of the hierarchy three other abstract 
sciences are recognised by Masaryk — namely, VIII. 
Philology (Sprachforschung, including Sprachlehre 
und Grammatik) ; IX. ^Esthetics ; and X. Logic 
(i.e., Abstract Logic). I do not deem it necessary 
to remark on that part of Masaryk's scheme, nor on 



282 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

his plan or views of the system of the concrete 
sciences. It must suffice that I enumerate them as 
given by himself: C. Concrete Sciences. 1. 
Geometry; 2. Astronomy (Chronology), Acoustics 
(in part), Hydrostatics, Hydrodynamics, Aero- 
statics, &c, Cosmography (Astro, Geo, and Oceano- 
graphy), Cosmology (Astrogeny, Geology, &c, also 
Cosmical Physics, Chemistry, Astro - physics and 
Astro- chemistry, Geo -physics and Geo -chemistry, 
&c.) ; 3. Botany and Zoology ; 4. Concrete Psy- 
chology, Ethnology, Political Sciences, Political 
Economy (including Statistics), and History (both 
Universal and Special) ; 5. History of Language ; 
6. Theory of Arts ; and 7. Concrete Logic. All the 
so-called Concrete Sciences are represented as in 
one direction or connection closely related to the 
Abstract Sciences, and in another to the Practical 
Sciences. 

Supplementary to the section of Masaryk's 
system of the sciences, as above described, are two 
sections of reflections exclusively on the concrete 
and practical sciences. Book v. of his work is a 
statement of his Philosophy understood as equivalent 
to Metaphysics. Theology he does not admit to be 
a science or group of sciences. But he treats it 
respectfully, and acknowledges it to have been a 
chief condition of scientific progress. He has 
written a valuable treatise, and discussed in it 



FROM MASARYK TO KARL PEARSON. 283 

with varying degrees of lucidity and thoroughness 
a great number of questions and problems as to 
the classification and organisation of the sciences. 
That he has often failed to arrive at definite or 
accurate conclusions, I am not prepared to deny. 
To excite thought, however, is often a greater 
benefit than to satisfy it. 

M. Adrien Naville, a worthy son of the illustri- a N»Tflie. 
ous Genevan philosopher, M. Ernest Naville, has 
earnestly and repeatedly occupied his mind with 
the subject under consideration. In 1888 he pub- 
lished a Nouvelle Classification des Sciences; in 
1898 he gave an excellent restatement of Le 
principe general de la classification des sciences in 
the German philosophical periodical Archiv fur 
systematische Philosophic, iv Band, Heft 3, 1898 ; 
and in 1901 a second edition of the work which 
appeared in 1888 is spoken of by the author as 
" completely recast " {entibrment refondue). He 
describes the purpose of the work so long dealt 
with as being to trace the boundaries of the special 
sciences, to distinguish the fundamental notions of 
each of them, and to mark the relations which 
connect them. His mode of distributing them 
has, so far as I am aware, the merit of original- 
ity, one now becoming rare among the classifiers 
of the sciences. It is by grouping the sciences 



284 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES, 

around three questions which he regards as funda- 
mental. 

The sciences he maintains are " wholes (des 
ensembles) of answers to questions put by the 
human mind, and the deepest differences between 
the sciences are those which result from the 
answers to the questions laid down." But the 
fundamental questions referred to are in his opinion 
just those three : 1. What is it that is possible ? 
2. What is it that is real ? and 3. What is it that 
is good? Hence he holds that there are three 
great classes of sciences ; and that those sciences 
which answer the first question are the sciences 
of limits and of the necessary relations of pos- 
sibilities, or, in equivalent terms, the sciences of 
laws; those which answer the second question, 
the sciences of possibilities realised, the sciences 
of facts; and, further, those which satisfy the 
third question — namely, the sciences of possibil- 
ities the realisation of which would be good, or, 
in equivalent terms, the sciences of ideal rules 
of action. His scheme of classification is entirely 
dependent on his principle of classification. 

His Tableau of the former is regulated by the 
latter, and determines his distribution of the sciences 
under the three headings — I. Theorematics ; II. 
History; and III. Canonics. As belonging to I. 
Theorematics, he mentions the following sciences : 



FROM MASAKYK TO KARL PEARSON. 285 

(1) Nomology, (2) Arithmology, (3) Geometry, (4) 
Kinematics, (5) Physico-Chemistry, (6) Biology, (7) 
Psychology, and (8) Sociology. He acknowledges, 
however, that there may be many more sciences of 
mere laws, and even an indefinite number of them. 
What he regards as the science of laws under an 
absolutely abstract form is what he calls nomology ; 
arithmology (arithmetic and algebra), geometry, and 
kinematics are at once mathematical sciences and 
sciences of law ; but there are other mathematical 
sciences, and, even if there were not, there is a vast 
interval between the mathematical and the physical 
sciences, and a still vaster between the former and 
psychology and sociology. That psychology and 
sociology are occupied merely with the possible, not 
with the real, is extremely questionable, and indeed 
M. fraville himself admits that we do not yet possess 
a truly theorematic psychology or sociology; that 
they are not universally considered as sciences of 
laws, but are, on the contrary, largely composed of 
historical generalisations derived from experience. 
Herbert Spencer placed them in the same class as 
astronomy, geology, mineralogy, &c, which are 
certainly more occupied with the real than with 
the possible. That the mathematical sciences are 
sciences of possibilities and theorems and not of 
realities or facts is not likely to be denied, nor 
will it be doubted that they are members of a 



286 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

very distinct and special group of sciences which, 
although not wholly unrelated to psychology and 
sociology, are no more related to them than to many 
other disciplines which M. Naville himself does not 
include among his so-called theorematic sciences. 
M. Naville's distinction between laws and facts, 
possibilities and realities, seems to me to be a real 
and important one, but also one which he somewhat 
misapplies and makes too much of. 

II. History, the second great section of his scheme 
of classification, is defined by him as the science of 
realised possibilities or facts. The signification given 
to it is very comprehensive, and yet, as we have 
seen, sociology is not included in it but in theore- 
matics, although it surely has as much right to be 
regarded as an historical discipline as most of those 
studies which M. Naville has represented as actually 
included in history. His reason for regarding 
history as he does is that it is the kind of know- 
ledge or science in which the question, What is 
that which is real ? is solved or in the way of being 
solved. The real is part of the possible, the possible 
so far as realised, what presupposes no mere con- 
ditions, no contingencies, no ifs. It is concerned 
only with facts and composed only of categorical 
affirmations. Further, according to M. Naville, 
history is not, strictly speaking, a class of definite 
and separate sciences, but, as he himself says, " a 



FROM MASARYK TO KARL PEARSON. 287 

single science without rigidly distinct divisions, 
because in concrete reality all acts upon all, so 
that in place of a series of different sciences there 
are only parts of one science." Hence the parts of 
history thus understood may be innumerable, and, 
as they already are in number and character, may 
be held to constitute the chief objects of human 
study. Naville's list of them is — (1) Astronomy, 
(2) Geology, (3) Mineralogy, (4) Botany, (5) 
Zoology, (6) Anthropology, and (7) Human History, 
political, moral, judicial, economic, linguistic, liter- 
ary, artistic, religious, &c. And they are all 
obviously to a large extent of an historical char- 
acter. But are they more so than say Sociology 
or even the History of Mathematical Sciences? 
Geometry, Biology, Psychology, and Sociology 
have all histories simply as accounts of them 
as evolutionary or progressive studies, and their 
objects would also have had histories had there 
been no human beings to study them. 

III. Canonics is the third and last section of 
Naville's classification of the sciences. He holds 
it to be a scientific group essentially different 
from Theorematics and History. It is meant to 
be the answer to the third great scientific question, 
which is also the chief practical question, and to 
include all sciences of the rules of human activity 
which expressly tend to the realisation of the best 



288 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

possible. A threefold division of it is given. The 
first (a) is Morale, the general theory of aims, the 
system or doctrine of rules relative to the choice 
of chief ends. Its function, according to Naville, 
is to study the different aims possible, so as to 
estimate aright their comparative and complete 
value; — aims held by him to be of four kinds, — 
namely, 1°. satisfaction for self, 2°. satisfaction for 
others, 3°. truth (knowledge) for self, and 4°. truth 
for others. He leaves it to la morale itself to 
determine the value of all special investigations 
into the nature of the good, and to show how 
their findings may be and should be combined. 
There are, however, in his conception of Canonics 
two other departments than Morale, a second and 
third. The second, (b) Theories of the arts, may 
be indefinitely numerous, inasmuch as they are 
held to include all theories which endeavour to 
formulate rules for selection of the most suitable 
means to attain ends of every kind; all arts 
associated with the various species of knowledge 
or games of chance ; logic and didactic ; industries, 
medicine, &c. Finally, as a third division of 
Canonics there are said to be (c) Moral Sciences; 
— sciences said to be composed of rules for the 
choice of the means best adapted to realise in a 
harmonious way human ideals. Paedagogy and 
the Law of Nature (or Reason) are the examples 



FROM MASARYK TO KARL PEARSON. 289 

given of them. The former seeks by all attainable 
means to develop to the utmost and in the most 
harmonious way whatever elements for good are 
contained in germ in the natures of children. 
The latter seeks to ascertain how the State ought 
so to constrain and regulate the power intrusted 
to it as to contribute as much as possible to the 
physical, intellectual, and moral development of 
all classes in a nation. 

M. Naville's classification of the sciences has now 
been described and as far as possible in his own 
words. My readers may criticise it for themselves, 
and decide, say, whether the section of Canonics is 
satisfactory or the reverse. Before coming, how- 
ever, to a definitive conclusion even in regard to 
Canonics, the seemingly weakest part of his scheme, 
they would do well to take into account that M. 
Naville published in the Revue Philosophique (No. 1, 
Jan. 1897) a very able essay onJEconomique et Morale, 
which may be held as a valuable contribution to 
what would otherwise have rather discredited his 
whole system, whereas now even Canonics may be 
deemed not unworthy of consideration. 

In 1893 M. Raoul de la Grasserie published his Deia 
De la classification objective et subjective des 
sciences, des lettres, et des arts. It is an elaborate 
work of more than three hundred pages, and obvi- 

T 



290 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

ously the result of long and earnest studies. Its 
author has attempted, however, an almost impos- 
sible task by undertaking to deal with three so dis- 
tinct classes of objects as arts, letters, and sciences, 
and with two contrary kinds of method, a subjec- 
tive and objective. Arts and letters are certainly 
not wholly independent of or unrelated to the 
sciences, but they are not sciences nor, perhaps, 
more dependent on the sciences than the sciences 
are on them. The subjective method of De la Gras- 
serie is any suitable order of method for a desirable 
course of education. His objective method is a quite 
different process. It is a tracing of the order of 
succession and dependence of the sciences in accord- 
ance with their own natures. As I have already so 
far criticised the classifications of Bacon, D'Alem- 
bert, and Ampere, in which arts, letters, and sciences 
are included, it seems to me unnecessary to dwell 
on what is akin to them in M. de la Grasserie's 
scheme. Of course he has not only studied what 
he knew to have been carefully attempted by the 
most eminent of his predecessors, but has also 
sought to appropriate and utilise what seemed to 
him to have true findings. Those from whom he 
has derived most are Ampere, Comte, Spencer, and 
Wundt. 

He has accepted as highly important the distinc- 
tion between sciences of matter and of mind, or 



FROM MASARYK TO KARL PEARSON. 291 

what Ampere called cosmological and noological 
sciences. It is a distinction which few thinkers, 
if any, have either altogether overlooked or re- 
jected. It is not a distinction, however, which 
can legitimately carry us very far. In proof I refer 
my readers to my criticism of Ampere's method of 
bifurcation based on the distinction. See pp. 79-82. 
Grasserie also adopts what he calls Spencer's 'lumin- 
ous division of the sciences ' into abstract sciences, 
abstract-concrete sciences, and concrete sciences, (a) 
By Abstract Sciences are meant those sciences which, 
like Logic and Mathematics, treat of ideals or un- 
occupied forms of relations in which phenomena are 
known to us; (6) By Abstract - Concrete Sciences 
those which, like Mechanics, Physics, and Chemistry, 
treat of real relations or the relations among reali- 
ties to which different modes of matter and motion 
conform ; and (c) By Concrete Sciences those which, 
like Astronomy, Geology, Biology, &c, deal with 
distributions and redistributions of matter and 
motion, molecules, solids, gases, organic pheno- 
mena, &c. As to the character of that classifica- 
tion see the criticism on pp. 98-103. Further, 
M. de la Grasserie has accepted Wundt's distinc- 
tion of general and special sciences but rejected 
the distinction of formal and real sciences. The 
latter, however, if properly drawn, is just as cer- 
tain and accurate as the former; and it is unfor- 



292 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

tunate that our author, while recognising how 
intimately the mathematical sciences are related 
to the physical sciences, should have failed to 
recognise that they are related also, although in 
a lesser measure, to the psychical sciences. Mathe- 
matics has undoubtedly a place and function in 
psycho-physics, human and comparative psychology, 
economics, ethics (moral statistics), and sociology. 
How far it will advance it is for the future to 
decide. 

Karl Karl Pearson, the Gershom Professor of Mathe- 

matics, has given a classification of the sciences 
in his well-known work the Grammar of Science. 
The work was published in 1892, and has gone 
through at least three editions. The classification 
is only dealt with in the last chapter. The nine 
chapters which precede it treat of a great variety 
of subjects bearing on science or sciences, as, e.g., 
the scope, claims, domain, or method of science; 
the facts of science; the meanings, progress in 
formulation, and universality of scientific law; 
cause and effect, as also probability; space and 
time ; the geometry of motion ; matter ; laws and 
life. All those subjects and others are brought 
by Prof. Pearson before his readers in a most 
emphatic and vigorous style, and with the utmost 
faith in himself and in whatever he affirms. Self- 



FROM MASARYK TO KARL PEARSON. 293 

criticism, however, is obviously not one of his char- 
acteristics, otherwise when writing his Grammar 
of Science he could not have failed to discover 
that he was really as much of the sort of meta- 
physician he despised as of the scientist he adored. 
He begins his chapter on the classification of the 
sciences with "a summary as to the material of 
science," and claims for "the heritage of science 
the whole domain to which the word knowledge 
can be applied," whereas it is philosophy as scientia 
scientiarum which makes that claim. No single 
science can reasonably do so, nor even all special 
sciences combined, as every single science has a 
definite and limited sphere of its own. Then he 
reminds his readers again, as he had been doing 
all through his work, that " knowledge is essentially 
a description and not an explanation," — a quite un- 
proved, and probably unprovable, generalisation of 
KirchofFs definition, not of all sciences, but merely 
of Mechanics. Whoever has looked into the Grammar 
of Science must have been struck with the contempt 
of its author for "the statements regarding force 
and matter current in all the elementary text-books 
of science," and his extraordinary faith in such 
phrases as "science description but not explana- 
tion," "conceptual formulae," " conceptual shorthand," 
and a host of other questionable phrases. Probably 
few books will be found less serviceable as an ele- 



294 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

mentary text-book of science than Prof. Pearson's 
own Grammar of Science if used as such, although 
being in various respects a work of ability it may be 
very stimulating and useful to those who can separate 
metaphysics from physics and rhetoric from logic in 
ways which the author himself has not always 
succeeded in doing. 

As regards the problem of the classification of the 
sciences, he approaches it with a clear perception of 
its difficulty, and even with an almost excessive 
humility. He recognises, to use his own words, 
" how incapable any individual scientist must nowa- 
days be of truly measuring the importance of each 
separate branch of science and of seeing its relation 
to the whole of human knowledge. An adequate 
classification could only be reached by a group of 
scientists having a wide appreciation of each other's 
fields, and a thorough knowledge of their own 
branches of learning. They must further be en- 
dowed with a sympathy and patience enough to 
work out a scheme of combination." * And again he 
writes : " An individual even with the ability of 
Bacon or Spencer must fail for want of specialists' 
knowledge to classify the sciences satisfactorily. A 
group of scientists might achieve much more, but 
even their system would only have temporary value 
as the position of a science relative to other changes 

1 P. 443. 



FROM MASARYK TO KARL PEARSON. 295 

with its development." l These are certainly words 
of soberness and truth. There can be no satisfactory 
classification of the sciences without careful dis- 
tribution of them into groups, a comprehensive ex- 
hibition of the connections between the groups, and 
a patient attempt to trace the relationships of the 
members of each group. The history of the classi- 
fications of the sciences is of itself ample proof of 
that. 

Prof. Pearson has taken into consideration only 
the schemes of Bacon, Comte, and Spencer, im- 
perfect although they be, and expressly tells us 
that his own scheme, which is derived from these, 
" pretends to no logical exactness " ; 2 and that he " is 
content to call it an enumeration if the logician 
refuses it the title of classification ; for he readily 
admits that he is not likely to be successful where 
Bacon, Comte, and Spencer have failed." But 
surely any scheme of classification should aim at 
logical exactness ; and to aim at surpassing the 
schemes even of Bacon, Comte, and Spencer need 
imply nothing presumptuous. The latest scientists 
have always an advantage over their predecessors. 
Further, how can a man be reasonably content to 
call a classification an enumeration, what it is not 
and cannot be ? A mere enumeration of the sciences 
can only be useless or worse than useless. Prof. 

* P. 474. * P. 452. • P. 452. 



296 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES- 

Pearson's scheme is nowhere merely an enumeration, 
but everywhere a kind of classification, one mainly 
composed of three other classifications generally 
recognised to be far from perfect but also of con- 
siderable value. 

It is a scheme composed of three sections — viz., 
A. Abstract Science. Modes of Discrimination ; B. 
Concrete Science. Inorganic Phenomena; and C. 
Concrete Science. Organic Phenomena. 

In A the general relations of discrimination dealt 
with are (a) either qualitative and quantitative, as 
also (b) relations peculiar to space and time. 

As regards the qualitative relations — Logic, Ortho- 
logy (by which is meant " the study of the right use 
of language, the clear definition and, if needful, in- 
vention of terms), and Grammar. As regards the 
quantitative relations there is a division of discrete 
quantity and another of change in quantity. Under 
the heading * discrete quantity ' Arithmetic, Algebra, 
Theory of Measurement, Errors, Probability, Stat- 
istics, &c, and under that of 'change in quantity ' 
Theory of Functions, Calculus of Rates or Func- 
tions, Calculus of Sums, &c, are assigned a place. 
Connected with the special relations of space are 
held to be Descriptive Geometry, Metrical Geometry, 
Trigonometry, Mensuration, &c, and with those of 
time Theories of Observation and Description (qual- 
itative), as also Theory of Strains and Kinematics 



FROM MASARYK TO KARL PEARSON. 297 

(quantitative). Abstract Science is represented as 
inclusive of all that is generally considered Logic 
and Pure Mathematics. 

B. To this second section belong concrete as 
opposed to abstract science and inorganic as distinct 
from organic phenomena. The common name for 
the sciences included in it are physical sciences, and 
by Pearson they are subdivided into what he calls 
precise or exact and synoptic or descriptive physical 
sciences, — the former being held to be those reduced 
and the latter those not yet reduced to ideal motions. 
Molar Physics, Molecular Physics, Atomic Physics, 
and Physics of the Ether are viewed as so many 
groups of Precise Physical Science. "In Molar 
Physics," says our author, " we deal with the motion 
which conceptualises the changes of position in 
bodies at the surface of the earth, Mechanics ; with 
the motion which conceptualises the changes in the 
planetary system, Planetary Theory ; and with the 
motion by which we describe changes in the con- 
figuration of a planet and its satellites, Lunar 
Theory." 1 To Molecular Physics he attaches 
Crystallography, Hydromechanics, Aeromechanics, 
Theory of the Tides, &c. ; to Atomic Physics 
Theoretic Chemistry, Spectrum Analysis, Solar and 
Sidereal Physics, &c. ; to Physics of the Ether 
sundry studies apart from and also in association 

* P. 461. 



298 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

with the Molecule, as e.g., Theory of Radiation, 
Light, Heat, Electricity, Magnetism, and Theories 
of Dispersion, Absorption, Transmission, Conduction, 
&c. The Synoptic Physical Sciences are the Theory 
of Inorganic Evolution, Geology, Geography, 
Meteorology, Mineralogy, Chemistry, &c. 

C. The third and last great field of knowledge 
according to Pearson is the division of concrete 
science which deals with organic phenomena. It 
includes the biological sciences, and he subdivides 
them into those which deal more especially with 
space or the localisation of life and those which 
deal more especially with time or growth. In the 
first subdivision he places what he calls Chorology 
(geographical distribution of living forms), Ecology 
(habits in relation to situation and climate), and 
Natural History (in old sense) ; and in the second 
History as non-recurring and Biology as recurring 
growth. History is further described as compre- 
hending the general evolution of species, connected 
with which are Phytogeny, Palceontology, Origin of 
Species, &c., and the special evolution of man, con- 
nected with which are Craniology, Anthropology, 
&c, as regarding his physique ; Art, Literature, 
Science, and Philosophy as dependent on his mental 
faculties ; and States, Laws, Customs, Archaeology, 
Folklore, &c., as inseparable from his social in- 
stitutions. There follow Morphology, Histology, 



FROM MASARYK TO KARL PEARSON. 299 

Anatomy, Evolution, Theory of Sex, Theory of 
Heredity, Physiology, Special Psychology of Man, 
and Sociology, the last branch of psychology, but 
also one which subdivides into such branches as the 
Science of Morals, the Science of Politics, Political 
Economy, and Jurisprudence. The whole scheme 
is brought to a close with Applied Mathematics, 
which link Abstract Science to the Physical Sciences, 
and Bio-Physics, which connects the Physical and 
Biological Sciences. 

Prof. Pearson has candidly acknowledged that 
freedom from errors cannot be claimed for the 
foregoing scheme, and certainly the errors of it 
are numerous. Logic, Orthology, and Grammar 
are the members of his first group. But of the 
three only the first is a science. So-called Orth- 
ology is merely a portion or function of Logic 
which almost all books on Logic deal with in some 
measure, but which it is an abuse of language to 
designate a science in itself. Further, what is meant 
by Grammar? and why is it located in the first 
group of sciences? Is it even Grammar in the 
ordinary sense of the term? In that case it is 
nearly equivalent to what Pearson calls Orthology, 
and there would seem to be no good reason for the 
invention of the latter term, and still less for count- 
ing the same science, if a science at all, twice. Or, 
Is Grammar to be understood in the sense which he 



300 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

attaches to it in the title and throughout the body 
of his own book ? — a book in which he pronounces 
judgment on the relation of science to theology and 
metaphysics, as well as on the natures and relation- 
ships of causes and effects, matter, motion, life, &c. 
Epistemology, Logic, and Methodology would, I 
think, have formed a much more natural group than 
the one he has given us. As regards most of the 
other group there is no less room for criticism. The 
author of them has trusted too much to Bacon, 
Comte, and Spencer alone; and has apparently 
not even looked at what, for example, Ampere, 
Whewell, and Wundt have done in the matter. In 
the edition in my possession he has not even re- 
ferred to them. He confidently denies the reality 
of either theological or metaphysical science. The 
closing words of his Grammar of Science are these : 
" We have a duty before us, which, if we have faith 
in the scientific method, is simple and obvious. We 
must turn a deaf ear to all those who would suggest 
that we can enter the stronghold of truth by the 
burrow of superstition, or scale its walls by the 
ladder of metaphysics. We must accomplish a task 
more difficult to many minds than daring to know. 
We must dare to be ignorant. Ignoramus, labor- 
andum est." l It is strange that a man of the ability 
of Prof. Pearson could fancy that by such rash and 
. l P. 474. 



FROM PAUL JANET TO PRESENT TIME. 301 

random words rational beings would be induced to 
ignore all theological and philosophical studies as 
superstition and folly. How daring to be ignorant 
can be profitable to any mind or any inducement to 
labour he has not told us and probably cannot. All 
labour and science presuppose a desire of know- 
ledge. That no one should enter into any burrow 
of superstition may be readily granted; that all 
theology is superstition must be proved instead of 
merely asserted. As to scaling the walls of truth 
with a ladder of metaphysics a good deal depends 
on the ladder, and Prof. Pearson may have been 
unfortunate in the choice of one. I cannot suppose 
him to be ignorant of the fact that an encyclopaedic 
study, a comprehensive and organic study, of the 
theological sciences, has had a far longer history 
than any other group of sciences. The history of it 
has been continuous through so many centuries, and 
on the whole so progressive and beneficial, that un- 
prejudiced men are most unlikely to deem all the- 
ology a mere " burrow of superstition." 



VIII. FROM PAUL JANET TO PRESENT TIME. 



From Karl Pearson I must pass to the late Paul 
Monsieur Janet, a man of very differently consti- ane 
tuted mind. During the last half of the nine- 



302 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

teenth century France had probably no more ad- 
mirable representative of philosophy than the latter. 
For almost fifty years a professor of philosophy, he 
made himself acquainted with all forms, phases, and 
departments of it; was, to use his own words, 
always ready "to seek its foundations, authority, 
limits, and signification, by confronting it with the 
data and conditions of modern science, as well as 
with the doctrines of the boldest and most recent 
metaphysics " ; and could most justly say, as he has 
actually done, nihil philosophicum a me alienum 
putavi. He has written many philosophical works, 
not one of which is other than valuable, and most 
of which should long deserve to be studied. His 
Causes Finales (translated into English in 1878) is 
the best work on the subject. Hardly less im- 
portant is his Prineipes de M&aphysique et de 
Psyclwlogie, published in 1897, two years before 
his death. The first twenty lectures of the first 
volume of it all bear more or less on the subject 
of the relations of philosophy and the sciences to 
one another, and also on the classification of the 
sciences. To them I must refer. 

The first lecture is an admirable discussion of the 
question, Is philosophy a science ? The second is 
an equally admirable examination of certain modern 
definitions of philosophy. The third and fourth 
treat of the criterion of philosophy. And the fifth 



FROM PAUL JANET TO PRE8ENT TIME. 303 

is an inquiry as to what is or ought to be the 
respective and appropriate functions of science and 
belief in philosophy. None of the subjects of 
those lectures are irrelevant to a study either of 
the organisation of science or the classification of 
the sciences, for the simple but almost always over- 
looked reason that philosophy and science are most 
closely connected, and that neither can in any form 
be wholly severed from the other without serious 
detriment to both. In his sixth lecture Janet 
gives an account of just five classifications of the 
sciences — namely, those of Aristotle, Bacon, Ampere, 
Comte, and Spencer ; and the conclusions arrived at 
are that the classification of Aristotle is antiquated, 
of Bacon superficial, of Amp&re artificial and com- 
plicated, of Comte simple and solid but incomplete 
and mutilated, and of Spencer more comprehensive 
than that of Comte but also incomplete and likewise 
burdened with defects justly ascribed to the scheme 
of Ampere. 

In his seventh lecture Janet begins his own 
attempt at a classification of the sciences, but 
distinctly refuses to commit himself to presenting 
a systematic and complete plan such as Ampfcre 
and Spencer had endeavoured to provide. He first 
proceeds to indicate the reasons which had been or 
may be advanced in favour of a linear series of 
sciences ; and then carefully to show that plausible 



304 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

as those reasons may be there is a fact of such a 
kind — the fact of consciousness — which when care- 
fully considered makes absolutely incredible to sane 
reason belief in a merely linear series of sciences. 
Hence he falls back on the distribution of the 
sciences into cosmological and noological sciences, 
or into sciences of nature and sciences of humanity. 
The sciences of nature or cosmological sciences are 
subdivided into two classes. As regards the first 
group, these are the sciences which are concerned 
with the most general conditions of matter, and 
specially occupied with measurement, numeration, 
extension, and motion. Such are arithmetic, geo- 
metry, mechanics, and the still more abstract 
sciences, algebra, and the differential and integral 
calculus. Astronomy, physics, and chemistry, al- 
though less abstract and comparatively concrete, 
are placed in the same group and treated as 
abstract and fundamental sciences. Geology and 
mineralogy, however, are viewed as concrete sciences 
attached to terrestrial physics. The second group 
of cosmological sciences are those which treat of 
life and its phenomena. It also includes abstract 
and concrete sciences, — those which treat of life 
in general and those which 3tudy living beings. 
Biology is the science of life in general. As such 
it subdivides into three great sciences — Biotamy, 
Biotaxy, and Bionomy. Biotamy corresponds to 



FROM PAUL JANET TO PRESENT TIME. 305 

anatomy, and is the science of the structure of 
living beings. Biotaxy is the science of the classi- 
fication of living beings. Bionomy corresponds 
to physiology, both general and comparative. 
Botany and zoology are two concrete sciences 
connected with those that are abstract. The 
sciences of humanity should follow in due order. 
They all rest on a fundamental fact, the fact of 
consciousness, and are divisible into three orders 
of sciences — (1) Historical sciences ; (2) Phil- 
ological sciences ; and (3) Sociological sciences. 
While distinct from the sciences of nature they 
are notwithstanding related to them. History, for 
example, is inseparable from geography, and geo- 
graphy is connected with geology and astronomy. 
Psychology itself is intimately united with physio- 
logy. To psychology as the science of the facts 
of consciousness lectures eight and nine are devoted. 
Comte's criticism of the science is shown to have 
greatly misrepresented it from his desire to get 
rid of it; and, following his example, some later 
writers have fallen into errors as to its nature. 
Janet has done justice to metaphysics by raising 
in lecture ten such questions as, Is there no other 
science or class of sciences than those already men- 
tioned? Is there not a science superior to, after, 
and above any merely particular science ? Is there 
not the science known by the name of Metaphysics 

u 



306 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

from the time of Aristotle to the present day ? Is 
Metaphysics not a legitimate and necessary study 
in so far as positive philosophy or logic of the 
sciences? Is it not so far likewise as a synthesis 
of the universe under the form of philosophy of 
evolution or any other form? Or as a critique 
of knowledge? Or as knowledge even of the 
unknowable so far as in any measure knowable? 
Or in so far as a final synthesis or as a synthesis 
of the sciences of nature and of humanity ? 

The lectures which follow those that have just 
been noticed are not directly occupied with classifi- 
cation of the sciences, but they have indirect bear- 
ings on it of very great importance. The subjects 
to which I refer are the relations of theology and 
philosophy (lectures 12 and 13), of philosophy and 
the sciences (14 and 15), of philosophy and history 
(16), of philosophy and geography (17 and 18), of 
philosophy and literature (19), and of philosophy 
and politics (20). They are all subjects of a kind 
to be studied and taken into account by those who 
would aim at a thorough organisation of the sciences, 
— all of a character indispensable to any one attempt- 
ing so great a task. By Janet they have been dealt 
with remarkable clearness and comprehensiveness, 
and with entire freedom from any kind of prejudice 
or exaggeration. Although not direct efforts at 
classification, they must indirectly be most helpful 



FBOM PAUL JANET TO PRESENT TIME. 307 

towards a thorough insight into the natures alike 
of philosophy and science in all their relationships. 

Monsieur Edmond Goblot published in 1898 an Goblot. 
Essai sur la classification des sciences, a work of 
296 pages. The spirit of positivism pervades it 
from beginning to end, although Comtek views 
and conclusions are often criticised and rejected. 
M. Goblot endeavours in many instances to be a 
more thorough and consistent positivist than 
Comte, and assumes that all philosophical ques- 
tions and conclusions properly belong entirely to 
some positive science or other. The assumption 
is one which facts are not yet found to have 
verified. No philosophical question properly so 
called has been shown to belong exclusively to 
any of the so-called positive sciences. Philosophy 
always of its very nature transcends more than is 
attained or attainable by a single exact science. 

The work of M. Goblot consists of two parts. 
The first is much shorter than the second, and also 
of considerably less importance. The title given to 
it is " The Formal Unity of Science " ; and induc- 
tion and deduction are represented as merely two 
stages in the development of certain sciences, not as 
two distinct methods proper to them. All sciences, 
even the mathematical, — arithmetic, algebra, and 
geometry, — are maintained to have followed the 



308 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

same method of procedure, one uniform or homo- 
geneous in direction as being alike inductive and 
deductive ; not two distinct methods separate from 
each other, an inductive which begins with groping, 
seeking, and finding, and a deductive, synthetic, 
demonstrative process. The accuracy of that view 
may not unreasonably be doubted. Possibly such 
plausibility as it may appear to have may be due 
to failure on M. Goblot's part to distinguish and 
separate the two stages of knowledge, ordinary and 
scientific. Mathematical demonstration belongs ex- 
clusively to the latter and higher stage. According 
to the author of the Essai, all true science tends 
to become abstract and deductive, the experimental 
as well as the mathematical That may or may not 
be so. Considering how far mathematics has during 
the nineteenth century extended its bounds, what 
thoughtful and educated man will venture to say 
where will be its limits at the close of the twentieth? 
There has probably been nothing more marvellous 
in the nineteenth century a.d. than the development 
and expansion of mathematical thought. 

The title given by M. Goblot to the second 
section of his work is " The System of the Sciences," 
and in that section he subjects to a very close 
examination the arrangement and classification of 
the sciences. As was to be expected, he has main- 
tained that of all sciences the mathematical are 



FROM PAUL JANET TO PRESENT TIME. 309 

entitled to have the foremost and dominant place 
assigned to them. They are, of course, represented 
as composing the first group of sciences. Arith- 
metic, algebra, geometry, and mechanics are held 
to be its constituent sciences. The first two, in- 
asmuch as they are occupied not with measurable 
things like space and motion but with pure quan- 
tity, measurement in general, are deemed entitled 
to be placed before geometry and mechanics. Geo- 
metry is placed next in order on the ground that 
it starts from the idea of space, the conception 
of extension, what is also directly measurable. 
Mechanics follows as dependent on the idea of time, 
and is viewed as including kinematics, the science 
of movements, and dynamics, the science of forces. 
According to M. Goblot it is the best example of 
a science which has become deductive as soon as 
its elementary notions have been elucidated and 
its essential definitions formulated. Like all pure 
science, he holds it to be entirely abstract, and as 
such altogether independent of the reality of its 
objects. He denies that the notion of mass is what 
differentiates kinematics and dynamics, and affirms 
the real distinction between them to be that the 
former is concerned only with real motions whereas 
the latter takes account also of possible motions. 
The sciences of the mathematical group are said 
to have no need of resting on experience as they 



310 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

are always in conformity with experience. A fact 
not in conformity with mathematical laws is an 
impossibility. 

The physical sciences are next brought before us 
under the head of Cosmology. In their present 
condition they are, of course, allowed to be experi- 
mental and inductive, but they are also affirmed 
to be destined to become deductive. The following 
is the list given of them (see ch. iv. pp. 128-156 of 
M. Goblot's Essai) : — 

Physics, described as theoretical and abstract 
cosmology and inclusive of various studies — viz., 
(a) the study of the mutual gravitation or attrac- 
tion of masses (barology), (b) the study of heat 
(thermics), (c) optics, (d) acoustics, and (e) dec- 
trology understood as not only the study of elec- 
tricity but also of magnetism. The study of molec- 
ular actions is also added, but only so far as confined 
to physics and consistent with physics and chem- 
istry being two quite distinct sciences. Physics is 
defined as the science of matter, but matter is said 
to have no ontological meaning — i.e., to be not a 
reality but an abstract conception; and by the 
indefinite possibility of bodies as space is meant 
the indefinite possibility of figures. Body is 
affirmed to be space occupied in opposition to 
space empty, but the physicist is told that it does 
not belong to him to say by what it is occupied; 



FROM PAUL JANET TO PRESENT TIME. 311 

that the chemist and mineralogist should be left 
to determine that. 

Chemistry, with which mineralogy is intimately 
connected, is characterised as special or systematic 
cosmology. The new conception here is said to be 
that of bodies as actual things. The body, the 
elementary body, is the atom. And according to 
M. Goblot the atom, although indivisible, extended, 
and impenetrable, has no sensible properties, neither 
temperature nor colour nor even resistance, neither 
solidity nor fluidity. He has strangely little to say 
of it, and virtually nothing of what others have said 
of it, much and disputed as that has been. 

Astronomy and physical geography are char- 
acterised as forms of descriptive, concrete, and 
theoretic cosmology. Cosmogony and geology are 
described as historical, concrete, and theoretical 
cosmology. The concrete and theoretic are what 
they are held to have in common. What is pro- 
nounced distinctive of them is that astronomy and 
physical geography are 'descriptive sciences' and 
that cosmogony and geology are ' historical sciences.' 

The last great group of sciences dealt with by M. 
Goblot is now reached. He has treated it at far 
greater length than either of the two correspondent 
groups which preceded it. It is composed of Biology, 
Psychology, and Sociology, and designated Bio- 
Psycho - Sociologie, a somewhat clumsy but ap- 



312 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

propriately comprehensive term, one meant to 
indicate three important and distinct yet related 
sub-groups of very important sciences — namely, 
the biological, psychological, and sociological. The 
fundamental idea, however, which one would expect 
to connect all biological, psychological, and socio- 
logical science, is the very reverse of clearly brought 
out. What it is I confess I do not know. Perhaps 
it may be the idea of finality, but if so, there is no 
definite statement to that effect. 

Physiology occupies in our author's scheme 
almost the same position towards biology, psycho- 
logy, and sociology as physics towards cosmology. 
As pure and abstract or general physiology it is 
coextensive with all biology, and is the science of 
all the laws of life, or more simply the science of 
life. It is in close connection with anatomy. They 
march side by side. Neither without the other 
would have attained to the full rank of science. 
The great stages of progress in physiology have 
been preceded by discoveries in anatomy, and 
anatomy without the researches of physiology 
would be unable to elucidate its own observations. 
Physiology indeed, as understood by M. Goblot, 
can only adequately accomplish its work by combin- 
ing and co-operating with such species of knowledge 
as histology, embryology, morphology, phylogeny, 
pathology, and teratology. Zoology he connects 



PROM PAUL JANET TO PRESENT TIME. 313 

with botany, and describes them as systematic or 
special and applied or concrete biological sciences. 
Anthropology he includes in zoology. What he 
calls biological geography he describes as a biology 
which is descriptive, applied, or concrete, and as a 
geography which is linguistic, economic, political, 
&c. He further includes palaeontology and history 
as closely connected in this section of his scheme, 
and as both occupied with ' the order of facts in 
time/ Apparently he has overlooked that that is 
true also of all sociological studies. Hygiene and 
therapeutics are appended as ' practical sciences/ on 
the ground that they are serviceable to plants, 
beasts, and men. 

M. Goblot next proceeds to assign to psychology 
its appropriate position in the scheme of classifica- 
tion of the sciences. He affirms its dependence on 
physiology and biology, and indicates the relation- 
ship between it and them. Further, he endeavours 
to describe what physical phenomena are and to 
show their inseparability to some extent from 
physico-chemical phenomena. As to what psycho- 
logy itself is, however, he has said disappointingly 
little, and that little is not of much importance. 
The comparative psychology both of human races 
and animal species is entirely overlooked, although 
it well deserves to be regarded as what it must 
probably soon become acknowledged to be — viz., 



314 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

one of the greatest and most instructive of sciences. 
There is a like oversight as to mental pathology. 

As a positivist of the Comtist type M. Goblot 
should bring his classification of the sciences to a 
close in sociology. Comte did so, and was in that 
respect self-consistent, but it is not evident that his 
disciple is so. Comte divided sociology into social 
statics and social dynamics, the former being the 
theory of the spontaneous order of human society 
and the latter the theory of its natural progress, — 
the one exhibiting the conditions of the social exist- 
ence of the individual, the family, and the species, 
and the other the course of human development. 
What M. Goblot does seems to be something very 
different. He appends to sociology logic and 
aesthetics, and thereby implies that logic and 
aesthetics are of later origin and rank than soci- 
ology. True, he speaks of them as the remotest 
branches of sociology, and thereby implies the latest, 
but he does not show that they are branches of it at 
all. The logic of Aristotle, who died in 322 B.C., was 
at least as great an achievement as the sociology of 
Comte, although the former preceded the latter by 
so many centuries. Further, if logic and aesthetics 
can be so located or characterised as M. Goblot 
represents them to be, ethics and economics may be 
equally so, and in that case more may reasonably 
be said for the priority of them all to sociology than 



FROM PAUL JANET TO PRESENT TIME. 315 

for the priority of sociology to any one of them. 
It has also to be noted that logic, aesthetics, ethics, 
and economics form a distinct group of sciences, 
each of which has a definite aim of its own and a 
nature akin to but not identical with the others. 
Thus logic is occupied with the nature, conditions, 
and processes of reasoning as its subject-matter, and 
with the attainment of truth and exposure of error 
as its appropriate ends. Thus beauty is the dis- 
tinctive object, and the realisation and enjoyment 
of it the final causes, of aesthetics. So ethics not 
only undertakes to study men's moral natures, moral 
relations, and moral histories, but also endeavours 
to direct and regulate their actions. And similarly, 
while the specific matter of economics is public 
wealth, its distinctive ends are the production and 
distribution of that matter in the most appropriate 
and socially beneficial manner. 

A favourably known Neo - Kantish philosopher, stadier. 
Prof. A. Stadier of Zurich, published in the Archiv 
fiir Systematische Philosophic (Bd. ii. 1, N. R, 
1896) a contribution to the subject in hand, entitled 
Zur Klassification der Wissenschaften. He had 
already made an attempt of the kind in 1887. He 
prefaced his scheme with remarks on the views of De 
la Grasserie and Wundt, which seem to me of little 
relevancy and less value. That he should speak of 



316 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

such attempts as " relatively rare " seems to me an 
astounding statement, which the present volume 
should amply refute. He starts by defining science 
as 'the most exact description possible of the 
totality of the representations given to human 
consciousness.' That may pass as a harmless 
statement, but Stadler, following the bad example 
of some other recent German writers, has talked in 
such a confused way about what should be meant by 
the terms " Beschreibung," " Vergleichung," "Mit- 
theilung," " Benennen," " Mittheilen," " Erklaren," 
&c, as tends to the reverse of elucidation. On 
that subject readers may consult Herr Otto 
Schneiders review of Stadler's Klassification. (See 
A. S. Ph., iii. Bd. i. 1-19.) 

The first and most comprehensive section of 
sciences in Stadler's scheme of classification is that 
in which the sciences are divided into those which 
come under the heading either of Erscheinungslehre 
or of Ideenslehre— either into sciences which rest 
on phenomena or on ideals, on what is or what 
ought to be. The sciences which have physical and 
psychical phenomena for their objects and forms are 
numerous and compose subordinate groups, of which 
the first and largest is occupied with external and 
physical phenomena, and entitled Korperlehre. 
The members of this group are classified by Stadler 
as follows : — 



FROM PAUL JANET TO PRESENT TIME. 317 

A. I. Morphology. — It is said to deal with 
phenomena and their changes as they are im- 
mediately given, and is represented as a generic 
science of which those others are specific — namely, 

(a) Cosmology, as knowledge of the external pheno- 
mena of the universe ; (6) Astronomy, the objects of 
which are the celestial bodies ; (c) Erdkunde, such 
an acquaintance with the earth as includes Meteor- 
ology, Geography, and Geology; (d) Mineralogy; 
and (e) Biology, conjoined with which are Botany, 
Zoology, and Physical Anthropology, which all deal 
with the study of organisms. 

IT. Chemistry. — It is represented by Stadler as 
dealing with external phenomena that are combina- 
tions of elements and as having the following de- 
partments belonging to it : (a) Analytic Chemistry ; 

(b) Synthetic Chemistry ; (c) Astro-chemistry ; (d) 
Geo - chemistry ; (e) Chemistry of Minerals ; and 
(/) Biological Chemistry. As regards Synthetic 
Chemistry, the syntheses are referred to as either 
inorganic or organic. 

III. Histology. — Is occupied with organic pheno- 
mena as combinations of vegetable and animal 
tissues of the smallest and simplest order. It seems 
questionable that it should be held to precede either 
Anatomy or Physiology as it does in the scheme, 
and questionable also that it should be given pre- 
cedence to Physics. 



318 CLASSIFICATIONS OP THE SCIENCES. 

IV. Physics. — Has many sciences assigned to it. 
It is described as being no less than synthetic, 
analytic, cosmic, astrophysical, mechanical, optical, 
acoustic, magnetic, electric, and thermal, which 
means ten sciences in one. But there are added to 
it four other sciences — Physical Geography, Physics 
of Minerals, Special Physiology, and Special Psycho- 
physics. 

V. History. — The objects of history are pheno- 
mena and their changes as given at different times 
and in an orderly succession. Belonging to it are 
said to be Cosmogony, Astrogeny, History of the 
Earth, History of Development, Autobiography, 
General and Special Biography, and the General 
and Special History of Culture. Certainly not 
all of these are entitled to be deemed sciences 
strictly so -called, however interesting they may 
be as studies. 

B. Seelenlehre (Psychology). — Is the science of 
mind and self-consciousness, but also intimately con- 
nected with the nature and states of a corporeal 
organism. Stadler assigns to it the following studies 
as sciences — viz., (a) Subjective Psychology and 
Autobiography; (6) Objective Psychology, Psycho- 
physical Anatomy, General Psychophysics, Special 
Psychophysics, and General Life-History of the in- 
dividual consciousness (Special Biography) ; also (c) 



FROM PAUL JANET TO PRESENT TIME. 319 

Comparative Psychology, Universal History of Cul- 
ture, and Special History of Culture. 

C. Seinsollende (Ideenlehre), knowledge of the 
obligatory and ideal, subdivides into Teleology, 
which has to do with happiness, and Ethics, which is 
conversant with morality. 

I. Teleology has the following subdivisions : (a) 
Pure Teleology; (b) Applied Teleology; (c) Euda- 
monistic Psedagogy ; (d) Economics ; and (e) 
^Esthetics. 

II. Ethics. — It is subdivided into (a) Pure Ethics, 
which treats of absolute morality ; and (6) Ethical 
Psedagogic, which concerns itself with the relation- 
ship of appearances to absolute morality. 

D. Mathematics. — Stadler regards the mathe- 
matical sciences as occupied with the possible forms 
of phenomena. He has contented himself with 
enumerating merely three such sciences — namely, 
Geometry, Arithmetic, and Kinetics. But are 
mathematicians likely to be satisfied with so 
few? Or, are they likely to acquiesce in the 
three that are mentioned being placed last in 
any classification of sciences? Is it not a fact 
that they have very generally been accustomed 
to see their sciences placed in the first rank of 
most classifications of the sciences? 



320 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

Stadler's scheme of classification must be credited 
with containing not a few good points and some 
admirable suggestions. As a whole, however, it 
is far from satisfactory, and many earlier schemes 
are likely to be preferred to it. I have already 
referred to Schneider's criticism of it. 

Trirero. Three years later than the appearance of Stadler's 
scheme the Classifieazione delle Scienze of Signor 
Camillo Trivero was published. It is a work of 
nearly three hundred pages, and one of the books 
in the Collection of the Manuali Hoepli, so termed 
from the well - known publishing firm in Milan. 
The book of Signor Trivero has been much in- 
fluenced by the treatise of M. Goblot that has 
already been under consideration in this volume. 
It may suffice to treat it briefly. 

Signor Trivero maintains, like M. Goblot, the 
necessity of classifying the sciences both from an 
objective and a subjective point of view. All classi- 
fications regarded only from either standpoint of 
observation are held by him to be necessarily very 
defective. In his opinion, as in his predecessor's, 
the sciences must be distinguished from one another 
either by differences of the facts with which they 
have to deal or by differences of the points of 
view from which the same facts are contemplated 
and examined. Differences of method, he holds, 
are not to be taken into account in any attempts 



PROM PAUL JANET TO PRESENT TIME. 321 

at classifying the sciences. He even denies that 
there are any such methods. In that respect he 
has gone farther than M. Goblot, inasmuch as 
whereas the latter at least admits that there are 
different methods correspondent to the stages or 
phases of development in all the sciences, Trivero 
denies that, properly understood, there are any 
different methods. There is " only one," he affirms, 
"only one that is good and scientific, the method 
which proceeds from the known to the unknown; 
and it is of little consequence whether that method 
ascends and is called induction, or descends and is 
said to be deduction, or proceeds horizontally and 
is termed analogy." These so-called methods he 
denies to be distinct methods. 

In the opinion of Trivero a system of the sciences 
should be presented under the form, as M. Goblot 
has said, "d'un tableau k double entree, avec 
* divisions horizontals ' et * divisions verticales.' " 
In that respect Trivero and Goblot are agreed, 
but neither of them has worked out a scheme of 
the kind to either order or completeness, and 
Trivero least so, as he has presented no justi- 
fication whatever of the "horizontal divisions." 
Holding all knowledge to be capable of being 
studied from three points of view, he should 
have shown what the results would be, but that 
he cannot be said to have successfully done. The 

x 



322 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

three points of view are affirmed to be the his- 
torical, scientific, and philosophic, and intimately 
connected with them are held to be * vertical 
divisions' of the sciences. It does not appear, 
however, from Trivero's scheme that almost any 
sciences of any kind are to be seen from his 
* points of view' or arranged in his * divisions.' 
The so-called first point of view is * history/ and 
in history * geography' is included, but not more 
than ' history ' is included in € geography.' Further, 
history began its course not as * science' but as 
'art,' as • literature,' and still is often that and 
no more. Gradually indeed it passed into a 
political stage, and even exercised much political 
and social influence. Later it ceased to be satis- 
fied with merely describing or recording historical 
actions and events, and sought for a full com- 
prehension and explanation of them. It thus 
passed into the stage of theoretical and explana- 
tory science, but with only a very slight addition 
to the number of sciences. Beyond the scientific 
stage there is admitted to be a philosophical stage, 
but there is no mention of philosophical sciences, 
and could not be expected to be, as for Trivero 
all philosophy is merely metaphysics, and all 
metaphysics is merely a search for the absolute. 
Thus far the sciences exhibited must be admitted 
to have been exceedingly few. 



FROM PAUL JANET TO PRESENT TIME. 323 

But a hierarchy of the sciences resting on the nat- 
ural objects and natural sequences of those sciences 
has still to be recognised, and according to Trivero 
there are seven of them. The first is said to be 
Astronomy, and to have for its object the sidereal 
world; the second to be Geology \ with the earth 
for its object ; the third Mineralogy, which treats 
of the mineral kingdom; the fourth Botany, 
which is occupied with the vegetable world; the 
fifth Zoology, to which the animal kingdom 
belongs ; the sixth Psychology, in so far as 
man is more than a mere animal; and the 
seventh Sociology, the science of man's actions 
and productions. That may well seem to some 
a very clear and simple distribution of the 
sciences, or at least of a ' vertical section' of 
them, but it is certainly also a very inadequate 
scheme of classification of the sciences as a com- 
prehensive system in which are many members 
at once distinct and related. Could there have 
been a science of astronomy worthy of the name 
of science had there not been prior to it logic, 
mathematics, and so far physics? If geology be 
pronounced a science why should geography not? 
Can mineralogy be a science if chemistry be 
ignored? Is the definition given to sociology 
one of which any sociologist would approve? 
Certainly not. It would be nearer to a defi- 



324 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

nition of anthropology. All sociologists are aware 
that to define sociology is a very difficult affair. 

In 1898 a J. G. Meyer published at Strassburg 
a book or essay bearing the title Das naturliche 
System der Wissenschaften. I am, however, quite 
ignorant of its character or contents, having been 
unable to obtain a copy, notice, or review of it, or 
even to find out the name of its publisher. 

From 1866 to his death in 1901 Monsieur J. P. 
Durand (de Gros) devoted himself to the study of 
classification with more zeal, perhaps, than any one 
in France or elsewhere, while deploring that even 
naturalists and logicians had contributed exceedingly 
little towards the development of what seemed to 
him might be, and ought to be, made a complete 
and well-established science of universal classifica- 
tion or orderly arrangement in every direction, — the 
science to which he has given the appropriate title 
of Taxinomy. The most important of his works, 
perhaps, is the one entitled Aperyus de Tamnomie 
GSnSrale, published at Paris in 1899 (by F. Alcan, 
dditeur, pp. 265). Too modestly he described himself 
as merely a pioneer in a region where he had really 
laboured for almost a lifetime, and seems to have 
found in it much which alike his predecessors and 
contemporaries had overlooked. A more earnest 
and independent treatment of it there could scarcely 
be. A vainer man who had done as much would 



PROM PAUL JANET TO PRESENT TIME. 325 

have not unlikely claimed to be the author of a 
Scienza Nuova. Yet few readers, and especially 
readers outside of France, would, I fear, be likely 
to do justice to such works as those of M. Dur- 
and, suggestive and instructive although they be. 
It seems desirable, therefore, to state that of the 
Aperqus there are two good yet brief notices which 
will be no great burdens on their readers. One is 
that of Monsieur F. Paulhan in the Revue Phil- 
osophique for April 1899 (pp. 419-424). The 
other is that of Prof. Bosanquet in Mind for 
October 1899 (pp. 531-535). 

Both reviewers have naturally dwelt chiefly on 
the main subjects of the works reviewed, — those 
which Durand himself called the Four Taxinomic 
Orders or Problems. The First Order is described 
as that of Generality or Resemblance. The classi- 
fications of botany and zoology are applications of 
it, specially included in it, and familiar to us in the 
relationship between genera and species. Induction, 
generalisation, and specification are processes im- 
plied in it. The entire order is based on the rela- 
tionship of genus to species and of species to genus. 
Not so the Second Order, — the order of Composition 
or Collectivity. It is founded on the relation of 
whole to part and part to whole, and has for its 
objects concrete objects, not abstract conceptions 
like those in the first order. The Third Order is 



326 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

the order of Hierarchy or Relationship of Rank. 
It is maintained to rest on relationships of sub- 
ordination, as, e.g., of superiority, equality, and 
inferiority. The Fourth Order is that of Genealogy 
and Evolution, and is represented as dependent on 
affinities of kinship under the three species of ascent, 
collaterally, and descent. Taxinomy was Durand's 
great contribution to classification, and it was with 
classification as a whole that he felt himself bound 
to see it as far as possible fully developed. A classifi- 
cation of the sciences was accordingly not overlooked 
by him. But he cannot be said to have given it 
any special attention. It would appear as if it 
were regarded by him as a comparatively small 
affair, the settlement of which could only be attained 
through a rational evolution of the science of taxi- 
nomy itself Study, he seems to have thought, 
the variations of all the objects and methods of 
the objects and relations of the sciences, and you 
will necessarily learn to classify the sciences aright, 
although so many have failed to do so. We can 
understand, therefore, how, although he dealt to 
some extent in the last chapter of the Aperpus with 
the classification of the sciences, it was to a very 
small extent, and led to no result of consequence. 

There is no apparent likelihood of there being 
fewer attempts at classifications of the sciences in 



FROM PAUL JANET TO PRESENT TIME. 327 

the present than in the past century. No one 
classification of the kind has yet been generally 
adopted. The number of sciences to be classified 
seem to be on the increase, and some of them are 
difficult both to define and locate. New sciences 
are generally found to speedily introduce others. 
An active philosophy is sure to agitate questions 
which call for settlement from sciences that had 
previously been dormant or ignored. The great 
increase of interest shown by scientists of late in 
classification itself is of itself evidence that classifi- 
cations of the sciences will not decrease but increase 
in number. Both taxinomy and morphology are 
obviously working in that direction under the 
belief of those who cultivate them that each science 
is to be carefully assigned to its appropriate posi- 
tion in an appropriate class. It does not follow 
that a correct and adequate classification of the 
sciences will be either easily or speedily found. 
It will certainly not be found in any single linear 
series. It is much more complicated than that, 
and seems to be always becoming more compli- 
cated. The older sciences are at least as fruitful 
as they ever were, and the newer sciences are now 
seldom regarded with suspicion, but, on the con- 
trary, rapidly adopted and warmly welcomed. 

Consider for an instant the positions occupied 
by those three recent and very interesting and 



328 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

flourishing sciences called Anthropology, Ethno- 
logy, and Sociology. There are, perhaps, none 
which have come more rapidly to the front or 
attracted more attention. Nor are there almost 
any sciences which have taken possession of vaster 
regions or more numerous provinces. But they so 
interlap one another at all points, and so over- 
spread ground claimed by all of them with almost 
or altogether equal rights, that it is difficult to say 
what are their external limits or internal contents. 
So far as they have hitherto been dealt with, any 
one of them would seem to be largely occupied in 
attempting to supplant the other two, while profess- 
ing to be entirely co-operating with them. 

Anthropology is a real and very important 
science, the success of which has been great and well- 
deserved owing to the labours of its many zealous 
students. In the United States of America alone 
there are about forty Universities, and in the 
majority of them several teachers of the science, 
anthropological museums, and various means of 
practical anthropological study. Great Britain and 
Ireland are not so advanced owing to their want of 
encouragement and support, but individuals have 
amply shown how much they could do, and how 
much more with ampler means might be done. 
There is happily one admirable institution in the 



FROM PAUL JANET TO PRESENT TIME. 329 

kingdom devoted to the study of anthropological 
science, and which is well known to have an admir- 
able organ in the Journal of the Anthropological 
Institute of Great Britain and Ireland, — a large 
annual volume now in the twenty-fourth year of 
its existence. 

Its eminent president, Dr A. C. Haddon, delivered 
on January 27, 1903, a very interesting address on 
Anthropology, Its Position and Needs. But the 
very opening sentences of his address are these : — 
" A peculiarity of the study of Anthropology is its 
lack of demarcations : sooner or later the student 
of Anthropology finds himself wandering into fields 
that are occupied by other sciences. The practical 
difficulty of drawing a dividing-line between the 
legitimate scope of Anthropology and that of other 
studies is so great that we are often told there is no 
science of Anthropology. This lack of definiteness 
adds a charm to the subject and is fertile in the 
production of new ideas, for it is at the fringe of a 
science that originality has its greatest scope. It is, 
however, only by a synthesis of the various studies 
which are grouped together under the term Anthro- 
pology, that one can hope to gain a clear conception 
of what man is, and what he has done." 1 And he 
adds : " It may be logically consistent to distribute 
portions of Anthropology among other sciences, but 

1 Vol. xxxiii. p. 11. 



330 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

the result would be that the subject would suffer, 
and unless a society like our Anthropological Insti- 
tute busied itself with the study as a whole, it would 
be developed very unequally. Indeed, to be quite 
candid, at the present there is very little direction 
in the evolution of Anthropology, or in the study of 
its branches." 1 He has further drawn out, with the 
fully acknowledged co-operation of Professor Patrick 
Geddes, a very remarkable scheme of classification 
of sciences, or at least of studies, all held to belong 
to, and even to be portions of, Anthropology. The 
scheme is represented as having three planes. The 
lowermost plane may be designated anthropological 
and even biological. Adherent to it are held to be 
the following sciences, and they are arranged in two 
parallel series thus : — 



2. Palaeontology. 


Taxonomy. 


(Ecology. 


Rational Phytogeny. 


1. Embryology. 


Anatomy. 


Physiology. 


Rational Ontogeny. 



The two series are included in the first and 
lowermost plane. Series number one is the lowest 
of all in the scheme, and on the whole lies beyond 
the legitimate bounds of both Anthropology and 
Sociology, Taxonomy and Anatomy. Neither Tax- 
onomy nor Anatomy belongs exclusively or dis- 
tinctively to Man. The same is true of Physiology. 

1 Vol. iii. p. 11. 



FROM PAUL JANET TO PRESENT TIME. 



331 



(Ecology is an ambiguous term, being employed by 
some, Hseckel for example, to denote the science 
of Economics as applied to plants and animals, 
and by others to nature-folk as distinguished from 
culture-folk. The term Ontogeny is employed in 
biology and psychology for individual development, 
as contrasted with the term Phylogeny, which is 
used to denote the process of the descent and 
development of species, and to explain the ancestry 
and genetic relations of organisms. 

The second plane with its two parallel series are 
manifestly more entitled to be regarded as of an 
anthropographical or anthropological stage than the 
first. It is, however, arranged just in the same 
way. It is the intermediate stage or plane, and 
its two parallel series are the following: — 



H. 



4. Palaeontology 
of Man. 


Racial Classifica- 
tion of Man. 


Anthropographical 
(Ecology. 


Rational 
Phylogeny. 


3. Comparative 
Human Em- 
bryology. 


Comparative Hu- 
man Anatomy. 


Comparative Hu- 
man Physio- 

logy. 


Rational 
Ontogeny. 



The man who appears at that stage is truly man, 
although far from fully man. He is not a mere 
animal but a social and rational being which has 
occupations and institutions of the kind distinctly 
recognisable as human. 

On the third plane man is seen to have risen, 



332 



CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 



aided by the stepping-stones of the stages I. and 
II., or what is equivalent, those of the series 1, 2, 
3, and 4. It is the plane or stage on which, as 
President Haddon says, "the limitations of the 
classification in the animal plane are largely tran- 
scended, " " all the enterprises of social man studied," 
and where " Psychology takes us into the inner 
sanctuary of man, and while it, too, has its roots in 
his animal nature, it flowers, so to speak, in a realm 
of its own. In the third stage, the uppermost stage, 
Ethnology and Sociology are identified without 
proof given. They should be treated as distinct. 
The uppermost plane is the last, and composed of 
the two following series of sciences, or supposed 
sciences, thus : — 



m 



6. Archaeology. 


Social Taxonomy. 


Economics and 
Politics. 


Philosophy 
of History. 


5. Evolution of 
Institutions. 


Analysis of In- 
stitutions and 
Technology. 


Functioning of Oc- 
cupations and 
of Institutions. 
Linguistics. 


Criticism of 
Institu- 
tiona. 



President Haddon and Professor Geddes have 
presented as a whole the planes, sections, and 
series of their scheme of classification. That, it 
seems to me, may be found rather too difficult for 
general comprehension. Therefore I have also dis- 
tributed it into parts and sections, without the 



FROM PAUL JANET TO PRESENT TIME. 333 

least addition, however, of my own. But there 
should be no difficulty in piecing them together, 
starting from the bottom to the top, as indicated by 
the planes L, IL, and III., and connecting the mem- 
bers of each series by the numbers 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6. 
In accordance with the views of the authors of the 
classification, Embryology is set down as its first 
term and Philosophy of History as its last. That 
may imply either that the intervening distance be- 
tween the first and the last link is vast or that it is 
not. Embryology regarded as a science is of very 
recent origin. Von Baer and F. M. Balfour were 
among the earliest, as well as the best known, of its 
originators. Eegarded as a history, an evolutionary 
or developmental process, between the present hour 
and the origin of embryonic existences, millions on 
millions of years may have intervened. Then as to 
the last term, Philosophy of History, why should it 
be where it is and Sociology left unnamed ? Socio- 
logy claims to be a science, and, if not the very 
last, at least almost the last attained, whereas Philo- 
sophy of History does not claim to be an exact 
science, although it has generally claimed to be as 
good or better. History is a very ambiguous term. 
Everything has a history, the world and all things 
therein, a molecule of matter no less than the 
British Empire. Whatever exists, whatever acts, 
in the heavens or on the earth is history, and that 



334 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES, 

which is purely and strictly history. The best 
narrative of history is only a verbal history of a 
real history, the history of a history. So there may 
be a science of history ; but the science of history, 
too, is, and must be, another thing than the history. 
And as there is a science of history, so there is 
a philosophy of history, and it must rest on what is 
actual history, not history of history, science of 
history, or itself, i.e., philosophy of history. Socio- 
logy may, and not without reason, attempt to be a 
Science of History. Philosophy of History may not 
reasonably do so, but it is bound to aim at being 
more than any mere science or any single science 
whatever. It cannot be difficult to recognise defects 
in the scheme of classification presented. To in- 
clude the Philosophy of History in Anthropology 
implies the impossible, the enclosure of a larger 
system in a smaller. And further, there are other 
sciences seemingly as well entitled to a place in the 
scheme as those which are there. The general 
utility of the scheme, however, may readily be 
acknowledged. Acquaintance with most of the 
subjects drawn into it cannot fail to be helpful to an 
anthropologist. Enough, however, may now have 
been said of Anthropology, as it has not yet been 
clearly and successfully discriminated from either 
Ethnology or Sociology, although it is manifestly a 
member of the same group. 



FROM PAUL JANET TO PRESENT TIME, 335 

As Ethnography corresponds, or at least should 
correspond, to Anthropography, so should Ethnology 
to Anthropology. Ethnography is merely the de- 
scriptive study of all ascertainable groups of peoples. 
Ethnology is in a stricter sense a science, although 
one intimately connected with and greatly aided by 
Ethnography. The latter is occupied with the ob- 
servation of human groups and organisations, of 
hordes, clans, races, peoples, and nations, or, in 
other words, with the status, occupations, and insti- 
tutions of mankind, whereas the former aims at 
carrying out the fullest possible investigation and 
explanation of all that Ethnography may have dis- 
covered and described. Keane's Ethnology is an 
admirable exposition of the science so called. It 
deals in a singularly lucid style alike with the funda- 
mental ethnical problems and the primary ethnical 
groups. The work issued from the Cambridge Uni- 
versity Press in 1896. As regards the accumulation 
of ethnographical and ethnological facts and theories, 
perhaps the Zeitschri/t fur Ethnologie : Organ der 
Berliner Gesellschaft fur Anthropologie 3 Ethno- 
logie, und Urgeschichte, founded in 1869, has not 
been surpassed, owing doubtless to having started 
with the support of such indefatigable workers as 
A. Bastian, R. Hartmann, and E. Virchow. 

Sociology is an advance on Ethnology, as Ethno- 
logy is on Anthropology. It has often been referred 



336 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

to in this work in connection with the views of it 
given by Comte, Spencer, J. S. Masaryk, De Koberty, 
and many others. Very opposite views of it are 
still given by equally able men. For instance, Prof. 
Giddings, a most distinguished American thinker 
and economist, published in 1897 his Principles of 
Sociology, a work in which the nature of sociology 
as a science, of its place among the sciences, of its 
appropriate method, its territory, and distribution of 
parts, &c, were most skilfully exhibited. In the 
same year, however, a very subtle and elaborate 
attempt was made by Prof. Hyslop of Columbia 
University, in a Supplementary Number of the 
American Journal of Sociology, to refute the 
views of his predecessor. There he dealt with 
Prof. Giddings' classification in detail, and exam- 
ined and criticised a number of possible systems 
regarding the relations between Sociology and all 
its cognate and auxiliary sciences, or sources of 
knowledge. 

In America, and all the chief countries of Europe, 
Sociology has now attracted to itself a wide, vivid, 
and growingly increasing interest. Perhaps its im- 
portance has been most adequately realised in the 
United States, where it has been taught in almost 
all their Universities, and in a generally inde- 
pendent and practical way. Britain must be 
admitted to have lagged behind, but has now 



FROM PAUL JANET TO PRESENT TIME. 337 

seemingly awakened up to its duty and interests in 
the matter. The newly formed Sociological Society 
starts on right lines, and promises to be worthy of 
what it should be. It is to be hoped that it may 
have, as so many other countries already have, an ap- 
propriate literary organ for such a science as Socio- 
logy is. Of such an organ the AnnSe Sociologique^ 
founded in 1896, and since then till now directed 
by M. Durkheim and an able body of collaborateurs, 
seems to be an excellent model. The distribution 
of the matter in it appears to be about as appro- 
priate as possible. Little that is relevant to what 
Sociology is seems to escape the sociological net, or 
to fail to find in it something that may be of use. 
The classification in the Annie is from its first year 
(1896-1897) to its present year (1903-1904) scarcely 
at all altered, — a fact which shows that the scheme 
had been maturely conceived from the first. An 
"Analysis of the Sociological Literature (in Books 
and in Periodicals) summarised in the Annie 
Sociologique for 1902 " will be found at the close 
of a very valuable paper by Mr Victor V. Branford, 
" On the Origin and Use of the Word Sociology, 
and on the Relation of Sociological to other Studies 
and to Practical Problems." The great variety of 
classifications of the contents of Sociology to be 
found in books and pamphlets at the present time 
should not be regarded as in any way disproving or 



338 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

discrediting the validity and worth of Sociology. 
It shows merely that Sociology as the general social 
science is an extremely comprehensive science when 
compared or contrasted with the special social sciences 
which are occupied with the composition, elements, 
and internal organisation of social groups within 
comparatively limited spheres. There are many 
'approaches/ as Prof. Geddes says, to Sociology. 
There are likewise many sections, and also sub- 
sections, each of which has its own special charac- 
teristics, and depends on distinctive phenomena 
(statistical, physical, organic, psychical, anthropo- 
logical, ethnological, or theological), yet which none 
the less belong to Sociology itself. 1 

I must now hasten to a close. My history of the 
classifications of the sciences may be said to be 
ended, and a few concluding words are all that 
seem called for. 

I have not meant the book to be more than what 
its title means, and I have brought the history con- 
tained in it down to the present time. That that 
history is needed, no one, I think, for whom it has 
been intended, can fail to acknowledge. It is 
meant only for a certain class of persons, and 

1 The moet comprehensive study of the nature, methods, and aims 
of Sociology is the Sittema di Sociologies 1901 (pp. 664), of Enrico 
De Marinis, Professor in the University of Naples and Parliament- 
ary Deputy. 



FEOM PAUL JANET TO PRESENT TIME. 339 

whether the class be a large or a small one I do 
not profess to know. It is a history brought down 
to a given date, or, practically speaking, the present 
day. I do not pretend to have succeeded in col- 
lecting and dealing with all classifications of the 
sciences, but I hope to have come nearer than 
any one else to success in that respect. I have 
little doubt that of those who take up the book 
into their hands there will be a considerable pro- 
portion who deem its chief fault to be that so 
very many schemes of classification are presented 
in it. That criticism or objection will not touch 
me at all. A selection of comparatively interest- 
ing classifications is not needed, and it can be 
of very little worth to any one who wishes to 
have an historical view of the process of classifi- 
cation of the sciences. 

While I am writing these lines there is being 
held at St Louis, U.S.A., a Universal Exposition, — 
an International Congress of Arts and Sciences, — 
the express object of which is " to discuss and set . 
forth the unification and mutual relations of the 
sciences, and to thus overcome the lack of relation 
and harmony in the scattered specialists sciences of 
our day." There has never, so far as I am aware, 
been known in the history of the world any such 
event in the history of classifications of the sciences, 
and if that event be a success the latter history, — 



340 CLASSIFICATIONS OF THE SCIENCES. 

the history of classifications of the sciences, — far 
from being ended or drawing near to a close, must 
receive an altogether exceptionally powerful pro- 
gressive impetus. 

Considering the character of the arrangements 
and the qualifications of those to whom they are 
intrusted, there is every likelihood that the event 
will be a great success. 



THE END. 



PEIMTKD BT WILLIAM BLACKWOOD AND BOSS. 



WORKS BY PROFESSOR FLINT. 



STUDIES ON THEOLOGICAL* BIBLICAL, AND 
OTHER SUBJECTS. 

7s. 6d. net. [In thepreti. 

HISTORICAL PHILOSOPHY IN FRANCE AND 

FRENCH BELGIUM AND SWITZERLAND. 

8vo, 21s. 

AGNOSTICISM. 
Demy 8vo, 18s. net. 

THEISM. 
Tenth Edition, Revised. Grown 8vo, 7s. 6d. 

" A work of the rarest excellence and of the highest value as an incisive and 
powerful weapon of intellectual warfare directed against the materialistic and 
theistical tendencies of the day."— Evening Standard. 

ANTI-THEISTIC THEORIES. 

Sixth Edition, Revised. Crown 8vo, 10s. 6d. 

"These are not simply the lectures of an apologetic theologian, but of one who 
is by nature and culture a critic and historian of thought They are marked 
by wide sympathies and knowledge, lucidity of exposition, vigour of style, and 

cogency of argumentation the oldest and the newest ' anti-theistic theories' 

are here expounded, appraised, and oritioised. The book is a searching and 

honest and honourable criticism of the theories that seek to dispossess and replace 
Theism." — Academy. 

SERMONS AND ADDRESSES. 
Demy 8vo, 7s. 6d. 

VICO. 

Being the Ninth Volume of " Philosophical Classics fob English Readers," 

Crown 8vo, with Portrait, 8s. 6d. 

"Professor Flint has presented the pith of Vioo's writings with great clearness 

and tact He has indeed done his work in such a masterly manner that Vioo can 

no longer be said to be practically unknown in England. "—British Quarterly Review. 



WILLIAM BLACKWOOD & SONS, Edinburgh and London. 



SELECTED LIST OF PHILOSOPHICAL WORKS. 



PROFESSOR CAMPBELL FRASER. 

PHILOSOPHY OF THEISM. Being the Gilford Lectures de- 
livered before the University of Edinburgh in 1894-96. By ALEXANDER 
CAMPBELL ERASER, D.C.L., Oxford ; Emeritus Professor of Logic and Meta- 
physics in the University of Edinburgh. Second Edition, Revised. Post 8vo, 
08. 6d. net. 

BIOGRAPHIA PHILOSOPHICA. In 1 vol demy 8vo, 12s. 6d. 
net. 

PROFESSOR SORLEY. 

THE ETHICS OF NATURALISM. By W. R Sorlet, M.A., 
Fellow of Trinity College, Cambridge, Professor of Moral Philosophy, University 
of Cambridge. Second Edition. Crown 8vo, 6s. 

RECENT TENDENCIES IN ETHICS. Grown 8vo, 2b. 6d. net. 

PROFESSOR SETff. 

A STUDY OF ETHICAL PRINCIPLES. By James Seth, M.A., 
Professor of Moral Philosophy in the University of Edinburgh. Sixth Edition, 
Revised. Post 8vo, 7s. 6d. 

DR MELLONE. 

STUDIES IN • PHILOSOPHICAL CRITICISM AND CON- 
STRUCTION. By SYDNEY HERBERT MELLONE, M.A. Lond., D.Sc. Edin. 
Post 8vo, 10s. 6d. net. 

LEADERS OF RELIGIOUS THOUGHT IN THE NINE- 
TEENTH CENTURY. Crown 8vo, 6s. net. 

AN INTRODUCTORY TEXT -BOOK OF LOGIC. Crown 
8vo, 5s. 

DR THEODORE MERZ. 

A HISTORY OF EUROPEAN THOUGHT IN THE NINE- 
TEENTH CENTURY. By JOHN THEODORE MERZ. 
Vol. I., post 8vo, 10s. 6d. net | Vol. II., 16a. net 

SIR WILLIAM HAMILTON. 

LECTURES ON METAPHYSICS. By Sir William Hamilton, 
Bart., Professor of Logic and Metaphysics in the University of Edinburgh. 
Edited by the Rev. H. L. Manskl, B.D., LL.D, Dean of St Paul's ; and John 
Vkitch, M.A., LL.D., Professor of Logic and Rhetoric, Glasgow. Seventh 
Edition. 2 vols. 8vo, 24s. 

LECTURES ON LOGIC. Edited by the Same. Third Edition, 
Revised. 2 vols., 24s. 

PROFESSOR VEITCH. 

DESCARTES. The Method, Meditations, and Principles of 
Philosophy of Descartes. Translated from the Original French and Latin. 
With a New Introductory Essay, Historical and Critical, on the Cartesian Philo- 
sophy. By Professor VEITCH, LL.D., Glasgow University. Eleventh 
Edition. 6s. 6d. 

WILLIAM BLACKWOOD ft SONS, Edinburgh and London. 



'0